• <tr id="yyy80"></tr>
  • <sup id="yyy80"></sup>
  • <tfoot id="yyy80"><noscript id="yyy80"></noscript></tfoot>
  • 99热精品在线国产_美女午夜性视频免费_国产精品国产高清国产av_av欧美777_自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇_亚洲熟女精品中文字幕_www日本黄色视频网_国产精品野战在线观看 ?

    The Substance–Effort Paradox in Yangming Learning andthe Lesson It Teaches

    2020-01-03 10:12WangMiquan
    孔學(xué)堂 2020年4期
    關(guān)鍵詞:雙江王陽明

    Wang Miquan

    Abstract: Wang Yangming once said, “That which accords with original substance is effort, and only when one makes effort can one realize original substance.” However, this remark contains a substance–effort paradox: if people do not accord with original substance, they cannot exert effort, but if they do not exert effort, they can never realize and accord with original substance. This paradox is an important thread that runs through the learning of Yangmings later followers. Wang Ji and Nie Bao adhered to the first half of the statement, but their discussions of “according with original substance” are not without problems. Qian Dehong was more focused on the second half of the statement, yet it is difficult, if not impossible, to determine whether or not one realizes original substance. The crux of this problem lies in the conception of original substance (benti): it cannot be too near to experience, or it loses its ontological meaning; nor can it be too distant from experience, or the concept becomes purely abstruse. Later Yangming Learning was caught in this dilemma. Huang Zongxi asserted that “the mind has no substance, and its original substance is simply that which is attained through effort.” In fact, the ontological understanding of the mind and human nature does not prove effective in either explanation or argumentation, and in fact tends to result in dogmatism, mystification, and hubris. Therefore, we should understand the substance of the mind and human nature through the effort and practice of empirical human nature and the human mind.

    Keywords: original substance, effort, substance of human nature, substance of the mind, empirical

    The relationship between original substance (benti 本體) and effort (gongfu 工夫) is a basic issue in Song–Ming Neo-Confucianism. It played a central role in Yangming Learning (Yangmingxue 陽明學(xué)) and constituted an important thread in its development. Although this issue has been studied exhaustively, scholars seem to have overlooked the paradoxical relationship between original substance and effort. On the one hand, original substance is both the precondition and the final result of effort; without realizing original substance, ones effort is all in vain, wastes time and energy, or even goes astray. On the other hand, one can never arrive at original substance without effort. This forms an infinite regress, and both how to confirm ones accordance with original substance and how to begin with effort thus become problematic. This paradox was already latent in Wang Yangmings 王陽明 (1472–1528, a.k.a. Wang Shouren 王守仁) demonstration of the dao 道 on Tianquan Bridge and exerted a profound influence on the development of Yangming Learning. To some degree, later scholars of Yangming Learning sought to address this issue in various ways; unfortunately, they did not settle the issue but merely arrived at different approaches that contradicted one another. This paper examines typical examples of this paradox in Yangming Learning, analyzes its root cause, discusses the conception of original substance and the ontological status of xin 心 (mind) and xing 性 (human nature), and draws methodological lessons by reflecting upon this ontological approach.

    The Substance–Effort Paradox [Refer to page 83 for Chinese. Similarly hereinafter]

    Wang Yangmings view on original substance and effort is summarized in his famous statement: “That which accords with original substance is effort, and only when one makes effort can one realize original substance.” This remark seems to give a comprehensive and satisfactory account of original substance and effort, yet it contains within itself a paradox. Specifically, how does one confirm such “accordance with original substance”? One who has not yet realized original substance is certainly unable to judge this; only one who has realized original substance can do so. However, for one who judges that he accords with original substance, what allows him to confirm this? Here, those who claim to realize original substance seem to become a closed group who confirm themselves through circular argument. Moreover, how can those who are less talented confirm that the direction of their effort is “in accord with original substance”? For those who are already “in accord with original substance,” they do not need further effort, since effort is merely the aroused function of original substance. For the mediocre to whom “original substance is obscured,” they cannot possibly begin in their effort, for no sooner do they start than they go astray.

    Given that “that which accords with original substance is effort,” the effort of one who does not accord with original substance would seem to be simply futile. Notably, there was a tendency among the followers of Yangming Learning to regard the most fundamental effort as, above all else, the endeavor to accord with original substance. According to Wang Ji 王畿 (1498–1583, a.k.a. Wang Longxi 王龍溪), just as an unfertilized egg does not hatch, exerting effort without according with original substance is a waste of time and effort. Wang Ji thus advocated “l(fā)earning that preserves the a priori integrity of the mind.” Wang Ji thought it made effort complicated and difficult to exert effort on ones intentions (yi 意), constantly check and restrain ones feelings and desires, and strive to avoid making mistakes. Exerting effort on ones intentions is not the most fundamental effort. Rather, one should “base oneself on the a priori substance of the mind”; that is, one should first lay the solid foundation of intuitive knowledge (liangzhi 良知), so as to free oneself from the shackles of emotions and desires without the need for precaution or scrutiny. This is also what Wang Yangming meant when he said, “[one] has accomplished his task as soon as he has apprehended original substance.”

    Wang Jis purpose is easy to understand; however, this interpretation of effort faces a tricky problem when it comes to practice. Although a distinction can theoretically be made between the substance of the original mind and the function of aroused intentions, it is impossible to distinguish between the two in concrete mental activities. Intuitive knowledge, in the final analysis, can be viewed as a kind of mental activity based on human experience; the contents of intuitive knowledge can be grasped concretely through mental experience, yet its ontological meaning cannot be comprehended in this way. In fact, how to establish this ontological status of intuitive knowledge is itself a problem. When scholars aim to preserve the “a priori integrity of the mind,” it would seem that they still in fact revert to concrete mental activities, expressed in the form of aroused “intentions,” without any way to maintain their “a priori” (xiantian 先天) status.

    Wang Jis solution to the problem was in line with the thought that “substance and function have a single source.” On the one hand, Wang Ji distinguished between the a priori and a posteriori, and highlighted the more direct and fundamental effort of “basing oneself on the a priori substance of the mind.” On the other hand, Wang Ji also acknowledged that “the a priori does not exist independent of the a posteriori.” However, following this line of thinking, Wang Jis theory falters on two accounts. With regard to its emphasis on substance, since preserving the a priori integrity of the mind cannot be entirely separated from mental activity in practice, the theory has been accused of confusing intuitive knowledge, which is ontological, with ordinary acts of perception, thus undermining its ontological strength. With regard its emphasis on effort, Wang Jis theory aimed to attain function by directly establishing substance, and hence left no room for the practical learning of making ones intentions sincere.

    A common feature of the followers of Yangming Learning was their pursuit of a kind of fundamental effort of “according with original substance.” In this respect, the school of “returning to quietude” (guiji 歸寂), of which Nie Bao 聶豹 (1487–1563, a.k.a. Nie Shuangjiang 聶雙江) was the leading exponent, was a development of Wang Jis thought.

    If Wang Ji did not give a fully ontological account of substance, with substance still unavoidably entangled with empirical mental activities, Nie Bao took a more ontological stance toward the substance of the mind. Nie said, “To say that the mind has no stable substance fails to grasp the truth of the substance of the mind. This substance shines brightly within the mind. Silent and still, it serves as the foundation for the myriad transformations. It is the stable substance.” This “stable substance” was kept clearly apart from empirical mental activities. Nie said,

    Intuitive knowledge is originally quiet, and only when it responds to external things is there knowledge. Hence one must not equate the knowledge thus aroused with intuitive knowledge, and forget from whence this aroused knowledge comes. The mind resides inside, and in responding to external things, it casts its shadows outside. One must not equate the shadows outside with the mind inside, and search for the mind externally. Therefore, a scholar in pursuit of the Way seeks the quiet mind that resides internally, and preserves its quietude in constant stability.

    Nie drew a clear distinction between the “arousal” (fa 發(fā)) of knowledge and “the site from which arousal comes,” that is, between empirical mental activities and the substance of the mind. The substance of the mind is quiet (ji 寂), so the fundamental effort is to return to this substance which is quiet and resides internally. Nie believed the extension of intuitive knowledge consisted in returning to this quiet substance. Once this quiet substance is established, responses to the outside naturally become interconnected. In general, compared with Wang Jis monism of the unified source of substance and function, Nie Baos thought had strong dualistic tendencies, drawing clear lines of demarcation between original substance and aroused function, the state before arousal and the already aroused, quietude and responsiveness, and the extension of knowledge and the investigation of things. In this way, Nie not only highlighted the status of original substance, but also clarified the distinctive form of effort revolving around original substance (embracing stillness and returning to quietude).

    Nie Baos theory of embracing stillness and returning to quietude can be traced back to the Daonan School in the Song dynasty (960–1279), which was marked by the tradition of “realizing in stillness the state of the great substance prior to arousal.” However, Nies theory was still heavily imbued with the characteristics of the Learning of the Mind in the Ming dynasty (1368–1644), with a clear awareness of the “substance of the mind.” While the Daonan School was more focused on the experience of the unity of the myriad things, owing to its adherence to the theory of Heavenly principle, Ming dynasty Learning of the Mind was more focused on the centrality of the self, largely owing to its awareness of the “substance of the mind.” A feature shared by both of them is a certain quality of mysticism. Regardless of whether original substance was regarded as principle or mind, the way to recognize original substance was always a tricky problem. Indeed, mysticism was a logical direction to take, since original substance cannot be too close to human experience, or else it tends to become entangled with human experience to the detriment of the status proper to ontology. Mysticism set substance apart from the experiential and mundane, and brought into sharp relief the intuitive apprehension of substance. Compared with Wang Ji, Nie Bao gave more emphasis to the substance of the mind, even to the point of risking slipping into a substance–function dualism. For this and for the tendency toward empty quietude in his theory of effort, Nie was criticized by other scholars of Yangming Learning.

    Qian Dehong 錢德洪 (1496–1574, courtesy name Xushan 緒山), another brilliant disciple of Wang Yangming, was critical of both Wang Ji and Nie Bao, charging them with “overemphasizing original substance.” Qian held the notion of “making ones intentions sincere” in high regard, and advocated “exerting strenuous effort in inspecting and restraining oneself,” that is, self-cultivation in daily experience where “ones likes and dislikes become manifest after being aroused by external things.” Judging by Wang Yangmings remark that “That which accords with original substance is effort, and only when one makes effort can one realize original substance,” the first part of the remark depicts the theories of Wang Ji and Nie Bao, and the second half that of Qian Dehong. For Qian, one can only exert effort on concrete mental activities, rather than directly on the substance of the mind. As long as “the effort made in making ones intentions sincere is supreme,” then “the substance is spontaneously quiet, and ones responses spontaneously appropriate.”

    Evidently, Qian was not as concerned as Wang Ji and Nie Bao with the “substance of the mind”; he put more emphasis on effort in the empirical world. According to Zhang Xuezhi 張學(xué)智, some of Qians theories were a “precursor to Huang Zongxis thought that the mind has no substance, and its original substance is simply that which is attained through effort.” As convincing as Qians argument seems, it was criticized by those who emphasized substance as blurring the boundary between substance and function, with the consequence that one loses sight of the essential by being burdened and confused in addressing the trivial and complicated task of inspecting and restraining oneself. In practical effort, such questions as how to determine whether effort has reached its “l(fā)imit,” whether is it able to perceive “substance,” and whether this process is as “spontaneous” as Qian believed, all remain doubtful.

    In summary, Wang Ji, Nie Bao, and Qian Dehong dealt with substance and effort through different approaches, and brought into sharp focus the substance–effort paradox discussed at the beginning of this paper.

    For Wang Ji and Nie Bao, original substance was of prime importance and was a precondition for effort, yet how can one determine that one has “realized original substance”? Wang Ji stuck to the monistic view that substance and function are one, and hence the substance of the mind became entangled with concrete mental activities. As a consequence, Wang Ji did not succeed in developing the theory he envisioned, that of directing effort straight to substance. Nie Bao risked dividing substance and effort into two by establishing “quietude” as the characteristic of the substance of the mind; eventually, he could not help but take a mystical approach to explain the realization of substance, making it impossible to assess. Although Yangming stated that “that which accords with original substance is effort,” the problems with Wang Ji and Nie Bao demonstrate that it is impossible to determine, in absolutely rational terms, the state of being “in accord with original substance.” In contrast, Qian Dehong took the opposite approach, going from effort to substance; however, the problem persists as to how one knows that one does not go astray or that “the state attained through effort is substance” without realizing substance in the first place.

    Therefore, it seems that effort is either simply unnecessary (for those who are already “in accord with original substance,” yet this state of according with substance is impossible to determine), or simply impossible (for those who are not yet “in accord with substance”). Hence, although Wang Yangmings statement seems comprehensive and satisfactory, careful reflection upon it reveals the seemingly insoluble conflict between substance and effort in such a framework. It was indeed precisely their problematic relationship that also set later scholars of Yangming Learning, such as Wang Ji, Nie Bao, and Qian Dehong, in disagreement with each other.

    Reflections on the Substance of Human Nature and the Mind [88]

    How did the above substance–effort paradox come into being, and in what way can it be resolved? In this pair of concepts, there is little doubt about effort, and it is “substance” that is questionable.

    Since this paradox presupposes a transcendent original substance, on the one hand, the goodness of human nature and the possibility of effort are grounded, so “that which accords with original substance is effort”; on the other hand, worldly effort seems to obtain a transcendent goal and destination, so “only when one makes effort can one realize original substance.” However, one is faced with a dilemma as soon as one seeks to understand this transcendent substance: it cannot be too near to experience or it may reduce the transcendence of the substance; neither can it be too distant from experience or it will become speculative or mystical, doing no good or even harm to practice. This dilemma is the cause of the Yangming substance–effort paradox, and the source of the disagreement among Wang Ji, Nie Bao, Qian Dehong, and other scholars. With the development of the Learning of the Mind, Huang Zongxi 黃宗羲 (1610–1695) advanced the opinion that “the mind has no substance, and its original substance is simply that which is attained through effort.” In Huangs interpretation, original substance plays a rather nominal role, and effort becomes essential, the aspect one that must attend to assiduously. In fact, insistence on the transcendent nature of original substance makes it impossible to resolve the substance–effort paradox; the paradox can only be resolved by setting aside the transcendent original substance and turning to Huangs theory that “the mind has no original substance.” The substance–effort paradox reminds us to further examine the ontological interpretation of the mind and human nature.

    To understand the substance of the mind and human nature, one has to understand how they relate to the mind and human nature in quotidian experience, or rather, how the substance of the mind and human nature reconcile with their functions in everyday experience. Generally, there are two ways to understand this relationship: one is bottom-up and the other is top-down. The bottom-up approach focuses on empirical content and effort on a daily basis in order to realize the substance of the mind and human nature, while the top-down approach focuses on the substance of the mind and human nature to grasp their empirical content and approach for effort.

    Cheng–Zhu Learning of Principle claimed that “human nature is principle” and, in this way, sought to prove the notion of human innate goodness. Since this approach begins with the substance of human nature, it is a top-down approach. However, judging by the actual development of the school, the top-down approach gradually gave way to the bottom-up approach. Zhu Xi 朱熹 (1130–1200) for example did not, as might be expected, develop an idea of pure principle–nature, or a substance of human nature; instead, he admitted that principle–nature still relies on qi–nature to be manifested. Thus, the dualism of principle–nature and qi–nature turns into a monism of qi–nature, with principle–nature being one of the elements of qi–nature. Chen Chun 陳淳 (1159–1223), a disciple of Zhu Xi, said, “In fact, the nature of Heaven and Earth is not separate from or outside of qi–nature; the point of singling out the former from the latter is to prevent the confusing of the two.” So-called principle–nature is singled out from qi–nature, but it does not exist independent of qi–nature. Apparently, after the Cheng–Zhu school, the principle–qi dualism and the concomitant dualism of principle–nature and qi–nature fell into decline, and there gradually appeared a monism based on qi and qi–nature. For example, Wang Yangming did not oppose Gaozis 告子 view that “what is inborn is called nature”; moreover, Wang stated explicitly: “Qi is human nature, and human nature is qi.”

    Cheng–Zhu Learning of Principle sought to defend the notion of innate human goodness metaphysically through the claim that “human nature is principle”; however, this claim is open to question. It is actually not because “human nature is principle” that human nature is inherently good, but rather precisely the opposite, that because human nature is supposed to be inherently good, so it was thought to have principle as its very substance. Consequently, innate human goodness does not presuppose that human nature is principle; on the contrary, the latter claim was deduced from innate human goodness. A convincing defense of innate human goodness must ultimately probe into human nature and the mind, so to prove that “human nature is principle,” one should first prove that “mind is principle.” This explains why Zhu Xi talked about “the mind uniting human nature and feelings” in his discussion of “human nature as principle.” In particular, Zhu proposed a new interpretation of Menciuss Four Beginnings in terms of their interrelationships: the feeling of commiseration is the single thread running through all moral feelings, and ren 仁 (humanity) is the source from which all other virtues like righteousness, propriety, and wisdom are derived. That the Cheng–Zhu school employed the view that human nature is principle to account for innate human goodness was probably due to the difficulty in making the argument from a psychological perspective, for as is obvious, apart from human goodness, there is certainly also an evil side to the human mind. However, it can be argued that goodness and evil are not mutually exclusive but related to each other in structural terms. For example, the feeling of commiseration is not only good but also preventive, inhibiting the development of evil in the mind. Therefore, evil also exists in the mind, but it is inhibited or suppressed in the system of human nature, and hence taken as a whole, human nature is good.

    Zhu Xis theory that the feeling of commiseration runs through the Four Beginnings and that humanity incorporates the four virtues can be seen as an attempt to buttress the notion of innate human goodness through a structural analysis (not merely an analysis of the components) of human nature. Wang Yangming proposed another structural analysis that differed from Zhus. Wang regarded intuitive knowledge as the foundation of the mind, and the feeling of right and wrong as the substance of intuitive knowledge. Where Zhu started from the idea that human nature is principle, and inevitably reached the conclusion that the mind is principle, Wang took a bottom-up approach, going from the human experience of enlightenment of human nature and mind to the opinion that the mind is principle. Both Zhu and Wang affirm the ontological meaning of human nature and mind. These views were by no means arbitrary: they were based on their understandings of the experience of human nature and mind as well as the concrete life experience of cultivation through effort.

    It is noteworthy that in religion there are two paths to the knowledge of God, the rational path of understanding the order of the world that is granted by none other than God himself, and the non-rational path of intuiting through divine revelation. The same is true when it comes to understanding the ontological meaning of human nature and mind. Not all took the bottom-up rational path, going from knowledge of the empirical contents of human nature and mind to knowledge of the substance of human nature and mind, and a few with fervent faith in the substance of the mind may have understood it through something very like a religious experience, and received guidance in thought and action the same way a religious person receives divine revelation. In its later development, the Learning of the Mind turned to the more non-rational approach, widening the gap between the substance of the mind and the basis of intuitive knowledge and practice, and the substance of the mind became a purely speculative and mystical concept that served like a first principle issuing instructions from above.

    To sum up, the problem with the top-down approach is obvious. The approach, at best, may encourage practice, but it does not prove effective in theoretical explanations or debates. For example, Cheng–Zhu Learning attempted to prove innate human goodness by proposing that human nature is principle, but this top-down path does not lead anywhere; moreover, it may lead to arbitrariness or even mysticism, like how the followers of Yangming Learning sought a way to directly intuit original substance through effort, such as Nie Baos advocation of returning to quietude. The top-down approach did not last long, and quite naturally underwent a shift to the rational bottom-up approach. This explains why Zhu Xis theory of principle–nature finally developed into a qi–nature one, with some empirical analysis of the internal structure of human nature and mind, and why Yangming Learning finally espoused Huang Zongxis view that “original substance is simply that which is attained through effort.” Both Zhus acknowledgement of qi–nature as more fundamental and Huangs predilection toward effort show a firm adherence to human experience and to the bottom-up approach.

    Conclusion [89]

    The substance–effort paradox in Yangming Learning teaches us a lesson that we should pass through ontological notions of human nature and the mind, and return to human nature and human mind in the life-world. In other words, we should restore the proper relationship between the experience and practice of human nature and mind and ontological theories of human nature and mind. The former serves as the foundation upon which the latter are built, and it follows that the latter must be understood through the former. Deprived of the foundation of experience, ontological theories lose their strength and rigor in explanation or argumentation, and provide no guarantee of innate human goodness or the practice of moral cultivation. If an ontological theory does not involve sensible self-inspection of the mind and human nature, or earnest effort made in self-cultivation, it is likely to make humans arrogant. In todays Confucian studies, we should see clearly and emphasize that experience is crucial to the notions of human nature and the mind. We should, in our research, be cautious about the meaning and function of ontological concepts such as the substance of the mind and the substance of human nature, and avoid sticking merely to the ontological, sacrificing what is real for what is immaterial.

    Bibliography of Cited Translations

    Chan, Wing-tsit, trans. Instructions for Practical Living and Other Neo-Confucian Writings by Wang Yang-ming. New York and London: Columbia University Press, 1963.

    Translated by Hou Jian

    猜你喜歡
    雙江王陽明
    真正心平氣和
    王陽明龍場悟道
    王陽明脫衣巧審案
    王陽明脫衣巧審案
    雙江縣總工會(huì):開展“三·八”維權(quán)周宣傳活動(dòng)
    良知
    李雙江歌唱藝術(shù)50年系列活動(dòng)拉開序幕
    李雙江:“想不年輕都難”
    李雙江 將軍歌唱家背后的真情
    搞女人的毛片| 国产精品国产三级国产专区5o| 高清午夜精品一区二区三区| 国产亚洲一区二区精品| 国产精品无大码| 极品教师在线视频| 一区二区av电影网| 欧美日本视频| 老司机影院成人| 日本黄大片高清| 少妇裸体淫交视频免费看高清| av天堂中文字幕网| 美女内射精品一级片tv| videos熟女内射| 日韩电影二区| 欧美3d第一页| 我要看日韩黄色一级片| 亚洲美女搞黄在线观看| 免费大片18禁| 国产高潮美女av| 婷婷色av中文字幕| 99热全是精品| 国产精品国产三级国产专区5o| 国产精品女同一区二区软件| av在线观看视频网站免费| 99久久九九国产精品国产免费| 99久久人妻综合| 美女视频免费永久观看网站| 一级黄片播放器| 美女内射精品一级片tv| 日本爱情动作片www.在线观看| 日本-黄色视频高清免费观看| 麻豆成人午夜福利视频| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 少妇的逼水好多| 欧美zozozo另类| 国产精品偷伦视频观看了| 国产免费又黄又爽又色| 久久鲁丝午夜福利片| 久久久久久久久久成人| 亚洲精品自拍成人| 国产一级毛片在线| 免费电影在线观看免费观看| 国产高清不卡午夜福利| 国产片特级美女逼逼视频| 肉色欧美久久久久久久蜜桃 | 免费观看性生交大片5| 亚洲经典国产精华液单| 黄色怎么调成土黄色| 国产在线男女| 色哟哟·www| 观看免费一级毛片| 婷婷色综合大香蕉| 91狼人影院| 青春草亚洲视频在线观看| 久久精品国产鲁丝片午夜精品| 亚洲人成网站高清观看| 亚洲精品国产色婷婷电影| 免费av观看视频| 日韩大片免费观看网站| 久久久久久久国产电影| 免费播放大片免费观看视频在线观看| 日韩欧美精品免费久久| 美女视频免费永久观看网站| 蜜臀久久99精品久久宅男| 国产成人精品一,二区| 大香蕉97超碰在线| 欧美zozozo另类| 精品少妇久久久久久888优播| 日韩强制内射视频| 高清av免费在线| 亚洲精品乱久久久久久| 日韩大片免费观看网站| 免费电影在线观看免费观看| 亚洲国产精品专区欧美| 久久久久精品久久久久真实原创| 精品人妻偷拍中文字幕| 亚洲av不卡在线观看| 男女那种视频在线观看| 亚洲精品成人av观看孕妇| 水蜜桃什么品种好| 只有这里有精品99| 亚洲人成网站高清观看| 久久国内精品自在自线图片| 男人舔奶头视频| 久久鲁丝午夜福利片| 六月丁香七月| 成人特级av手机在线观看| 精品久久国产蜜桃| 亚洲av电影在线观看一区二区三区 | 有码 亚洲区| a级毛片免费高清观看在线播放| av国产精品久久久久影院| 亚洲国产最新在线播放| 亚洲精品国产av成人精品| 国产精品久久久久久精品电影小说 | 日韩大片免费观看网站| 欧美少妇被猛烈插入视频| 狂野欧美激情性xxxx在线观看| freevideosex欧美| 日韩精品有码人妻一区| 亚洲av免费在线观看| 一级a做视频免费观看| 久久综合国产亚洲精品| 91aial.com中文字幕在线观看| 亚洲av国产av综合av卡| 精品人妻视频免费看| 精品国产露脸久久av麻豆| 国产精品三级大全| 免费播放大片免费观看视频在线观看| 亚洲欧美成人综合另类久久久| 国产午夜福利久久久久久| 欧美xxⅹ黑人| 成人毛片60女人毛片免费| 天堂中文最新版在线下载 | 色哟哟·www| 青春草亚洲视频在线观看| 少妇丰满av| 日本wwww免费看| 夫妻午夜视频| 亚洲自偷自拍三级| 精品久久国产蜜桃| 嫩草影院新地址| 午夜免费鲁丝| 久久99热这里只频精品6学生| 综合色丁香网| av卡一久久| 亚洲精品成人av观看孕妇| 直男gayav资源| 人妻一区二区av| 中文资源天堂在线| 女人久久www免费人成看片| 最近中文字幕2019免费版| 免费人成在线观看视频色| 亚洲美女搞黄在线观看| a级毛色黄片| 国产免费又黄又爽又色| 久久精品国产亚洲av涩爱| 老司机影院毛片| 美女脱内裤让男人舔精品视频| 在线观看av片永久免费下载| 久久精品人妻少妇| 男人舔奶头视频| 精品国产三级普通话版| 国产伦精品一区二区三区视频9| 哪个播放器可以免费观看大片| 久久久久久久久大av| 又粗又硬又长又爽又黄的视频| 久久久精品欧美日韩精品| 青青草视频在线视频观看| 国精品久久久久久国模美| 麻豆成人午夜福利视频| 中文字幕亚洲精品专区| av线在线观看网站| 久热这里只有精品99| 日韩视频在线欧美| 久热这里只有精品99| 黄色配什么色好看| 欧美三级亚洲精品| 久久精品人妻少妇| 九九久久精品国产亚洲av麻豆| 亚洲精品国产色婷婷电影| av卡一久久| 99热全是精品| 日日啪夜夜爽| 成年女人在线观看亚洲视频 | 久久影院123| 精品少妇久久久久久888优播| 精品一区二区三区视频在线| 男人狂女人下面高潮的视频| 国产乱人偷精品视频| 人人妻人人看人人澡| 亚洲成色77777| 午夜福利网站1000一区二区三区| 亚洲精品成人久久久久久| 亚洲精品乱久久久久久| 七月丁香在线播放| 国产精品女同一区二区软件| 婷婷色综合www| 亚洲人与动物交配视频| 晚上一个人看的免费电影| 亚洲人成网站在线播| 在线观看人妻少妇| 国产成人一区二区在线| 国产免费福利视频在线观看| 日产精品乱码卡一卡2卡三| 亚洲自偷自拍三级| 国产精品久久久久久av不卡| 美女cb高潮喷水在线观看| 少妇人妻久久综合中文| 色视频www国产| 国产精品久久久久久久电影| 午夜福利在线在线| 一本久久精品| 80岁老熟妇乱子伦牲交| 三级国产精品片| 如何舔出高潮| 精品久久久噜噜| 岛国毛片在线播放| 午夜免费男女啪啪视频观看| 欧美成人午夜免费资源| 97超碰精品成人国产| 免费黄频网站在线观看国产| 久久久久久久亚洲中文字幕| 日本熟妇午夜| 日本黄大片高清| 亚洲一级一片aⅴ在线观看| 丝袜美腿在线中文| 狂野欧美白嫩少妇大欣赏| 直男gayav资源| 成人高潮视频无遮挡免费网站| 日韩一本色道免费dvd| 亚洲自偷自拍三级| 少妇猛男粗大的猛烈进出视频 | 国产精品久久久久久久电影| 成人黄色视频免费在线看| 国产亚洲91精品色在线| 亚洲高清免费不卡视频| 人妻系列 视频| 日韩电影二区| 大陆偷拍与自拍| 深夜a级毛片| 男女国产视频网站| 天天躁日日操中文字幕| 99热这里只有是精品在线观看| 日韩一区二区视频免费看| 午夜福利在线观看免费完整高清在| eeuss影院久久| 精品一区在线观看国产| 国内精品宾馆在线| 亚洲av不卡在线观看| 美女被艹到高潮喷水动态| 亚洲av二区三区四区| 国产黄色免费在线视频| 丰满乱子伦码专区| 69av精品久久久久久| 亚洲国产欧美人成| 欧美性猛交╳xxx乱大交人| 亚洲欧美中文字幕日韩二区| 国产精品久久久久久精品古装| 国产综合懂色| 久久鲁丝午夜福利片| eeuss影院久久| 色视频在线一区二区三区| 久久久久国产精品人妻一区二区| 国产精品熟女久久久久浪| 国产精品久久久久久av不卡| 丰满乱子伦码专区| 欧美zozozo另类| 亚洲综合精品二区| 国产美女午夜福利| 欧美xxxx性猛交bbbb| 天堂俺去俺来也www色官网| 夜夜爽夜夜爽视频| 亚洲人成网站在线观看播放| 免费av不卡在线播放| 日本黄大片高清| 最新中文字幕久久久久| 97超视频在线观看视频| 久久久久久久久大av| 国产综合精华液| 大片免费播放器 马上看| 成年人午夜在线观看视频| 亚洲人与动物交配视频| 美女视频免费永久观看网站| 新久久久久国产一级毛片| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜添av毛片| 在线a可以看的网站| av天堂中文字幕网| 国内精品美女久久久久久| 日韩av不卡免费在线播放| 国产真实伦视频高清在线观看| 亚洲精品久久久久久婷婷小说| 国产黄色免费在线视频| 国产男人的电影天堂91| 欧美激情在线99| 51国产日韩欧美| 免费看日本二区| 联通29元200g的流量卡| 大陆偷拍与自拍| 亚洲av国产av综合av卡| www.色视频.com| 在线观看三级黄色| 一区二区三区四区激情视频| 国产亚洲av嫩草精品影院| 色视频www国产| 人人妻人人看人人澡| 日本-黄色视频高清免费观看| 精品人妻视频免费看| 久久人人爽av亚洲精品天堂 | 国产又色又爽无遮挡免| 精品熟女少妇av免费看| 哪个播放器可以免费观看大片| 欧美一区二区亚洲| 国产中年淑女户外野战色| 国产成人a区在线观看| 人妻夜夜爽99麻豆av| 一本色道久久久久久精品综合| 丰满乱子伦码专区| 亚洲va在线va天堂va国产| 亚洲不卡免费看| 搞女人的毛片| 亚洲av中文av极速乱| 狂野欧美激情性xxxx在线观看| 国产精品99久久99久久久不卡 | 国产精品99久久99久久久不卡 | 久久精品久久精品一区二区三区| 性色av一级| 内射极品少妇av片p| 2022亚洲国产成人精品| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 午夜福利视频1000在线观看| 国产日韩欧美亚洲二区| 欧美xxⅹ黑人| 免费电影在线观看免费观看| 欧美日韩国产mv在线观看视频 | 亚洲图色成人| 国产高清不卡午夜福利| 九九久久精品国产亚洲av麻豆| 色婷婷久久久亚洲欧美| 51国产日韩欧美| 熟女av电影| 国产黄色免费在线视频| 青青草视频在线视频观看| 在线亚洲精品国产二区图片欧美 | 国产有黄有色有爽视频| 一本—道久久a久久精品蜜桃钙片 精品乱码久久久久久99久播 | 蜜桃亚洲精品一区二区三区| 亚洲最大成人中文| 亚洲av男天堂| 一级毛片我不卡| 久久久久久久亚洲中文字幕| 夜夜看夜夜爽夜夜摸| 中国三级夫妇交换| 国产精品一区www在线观看| 欧美高清成人免费视频www| 日本与韩国留学比较| 国国产精品蜜臀av免费| 麻豆精品久久久久久蜜桃| 中文资源天堂在线| 2022亚洲国产成人精品| 校园人妻丝袜中文字幕| 99热这里只有精品一区| av.在线天堂| 大片电影免费在线观看免费| 中文乱码字字幕精品一区二区三区| 国产色婷婷99| 国产女主播在线喷水免费视频网站| 91久久精品国产一区二区三区| 超碰97精品在线观看| 日韩国内少妇激情av| freevideosex欧美| 少妇裸体淫交视频免费看高清| 欧美日韩亚洲高清精品| 能在线免费看毛片的网站| 不卡视频在线观看欧美| 亚洲精品成人久久久久久| 国产免费视频播放在线视频| 久久久久久九九精品二区国产| 精品人妻一区二区三区麻豆| 一个人看的www免费观看视频| 免费av毛片视频| 在线 av 中文字幕| 成人午夜精彩视频在线观看| 亚洲精品,欧美精品| 国产成人a∨麻豆精品| 亚洲精品乱码久久久v下载方式| 国产毛片a区久久久久| 色视频www国产| 免费看光身美女| 国产精品av视频在线免费观看| 国产在视频线精品| 男人添女人高潮全过程视频| 日韩av在线免费看完整版不卡| 国产高清国产精品国产三级 | 一级a做视频免费观看| 婷婷色av中文字幕| 人人妻人人澡人人爽人人夜夜| 日韩大片免费观看网站| 成年人午夜在线观看视频| 97超碰精品成人国产| 3wmmmm亚洲av在线观看| 日韩免费高清中文字幕av| 夜夜爽夜夜爽视频| 日日啪夜夜撸| 91久久精品国产一区二区成人| 在线观看人妻少妇| 国产免费一级a男人的天堂| 欧美少妇被猛烈插入视频| 成年人午夜在线观看视频| 亚洲无线观看免费| 日日撸夜夜添| 欧美丝袜亚洲另类| 国产精品.久久久| 最近最新中文字幕免费大全7| 特大巨黑吊av在线直播| 午夜福利网站1000一区二区三区| 激情五月婷婷亚洲| 香蕉精品网在线| 国产免费福利视频在线观看| 久久99热这里只频精品6学生| 日韩电影二区| 日韩中字成人| 老司机影院成人| 99re6热这里在线精品视频| 亚洲av.av天堂| 韩国av在线不卡| 国产成人精品福利久久| 高清av免费在线| 蜜桃亚洲精品一区二区三区| 精品国产露脸久久av麻豆| 久久精品人妻少妇| 中文字幕av成人在线电影| 人人妻人人澡人人爽人人夜夜| 国产视频内射| 黑人高潮一二区| 中文字幕久久专区| 欧美老熟妇乱子伦牲交| 新久久久久国产一级毛片| 亚洲图色成人| 欧美精品国产亚洲| 亚洲人与动物交配视频| 亚洲国产精品999| 国产爱豆传媒在线观看| 国产高清国产精品国产三级 | 日本欧美国产在线视频| 国产成人a区在线观看| 日产精品乱码卡一卡2卡三| 人妻少妇偷人精品九色| 久热久热在线精品观看| 欧美日韩一区二区视频在线观看视频在线 | 美女被艹到高潮喷水动态| 精品国产三级普通话版| 日韩免费高清中文字幕av| www.av在线官网国产| 国产欧美另类精品又又久久亚洲欧美| 人妻系列 视频| 十八禁网站网址无遮挡 | av在线亚洲专区| 男女下面进入的视频免费午夜| 春色校园在线视频观看| 波多野结衣巨乳人妻| 亚洲美女视频黄频| 精品人妻熟女av久视频| 精品久久久噜噜| 日韩av在线免费看完整版不卡| 一本久久精品| 国产毛片在线视频| 国产精品人妻久久久影院| av线在线观看网站| 亚洲精品亚洲一区二区| 亚洲婷婷狠狠爱综合网| 国产色婷婷99| 亚洲欧洲国产日韩| 精品一区二区三区视频在线| 欧美日韩综合久久久久久| a级毛片免费高清观看在线播放| 精品人妻一区二区三区麻豆| 久久热精品热| 亚洲精品影视一区二区三区av| 国产伦精品一区二区三区四那| 一级片'在线观看视频| 99久久人妻综合| 在线观看一区二区三区| 亚洲精品国产av蜜桃| 欧美最新免费一区二区三区| 网址你懂的国产日韩在线| 亚洲一级一片aⅴ在线观看| 麻豆成人午夜福利视频| 一个人看视频在线观看www免费| 国产一区二区亚洲精品在线观看| 极品少妇高潮喷水抽搐| 国产精品国产三级专区第一集| 久久久久网色| 国产探花在线观看一区二区| 高清日韩中文字幕在线| 亚洲精品一区蜜桃| 3wmmmm亚洲av在线观看| 成年免费大片在线观看| 制服丝袜香蕉在线| 18禁在线无遮挡免费观看视频| 搞女人的毛片| 中国国产av一级| 赤兔流量卡办理| 亚洲国产欧美在线一区| 九九爱精品视频在线观看| 2021天堂中文幕一二区在线观| av女优亚洲男人天堂| 波野结衣二区三区在线| 我要看日韩黄色一级片| 久久精品熟女亚洲av麻豆精品| 欧美日韩在线观看h| 下体分泌物呈黄色| 1000部很黄的大片| 久久久久九九精品影院| 少妇高潮的动态图| 嫩草影院精品99| 天堂网av新在线| 草草在线视频免费看| 欧美成人精品欧美一级黄| 男人舔奶头视频| 美女cb高潮喷水在线观看| 五月开心婷婷网| 日韩强制内射视频| 国产色婷婷99| 五月玫瑰六月丁香| 中文在线观看免费www的网站| 国产精品国产三级专区第一集| 色视频在线一区二区三区| 精品久久久久久久人妻蜜臀av| 亚洲av免费在线观看| 蜜桃亚洲精品一区二区三区| 日韩一本色道免费dvd| 亚洲人与动物交配视频| 亚洲精品aⅴ在线观看| 好男人在线观看高清免费视频| 网址你懂的国产日韩在线| 日韩成人av中文字幕在线观看| 80岁老熟妇乱子伦牲交| 777米奇影视久久| 观看免费一级毛片| www.色视频.com| 国产v大片淫在线免费观看| 中文天堂在线官网| 六月丁香七月| 国产精品一区二区三区四区免费观看| 国产亚洲最大av| 伊人久久国产一区二区| 26uuu在线亚洲综合色| 热re99久久精品国产66热6| 边亲边吃奶的免费视频| 国模一区二区三区四区视频| 久久久久国产网址| 美女xxoo啪啪120秒动态图| 精品一区二区三卡| 国产av不卡久久| av线在线观看网站| 久久99热这里只有精品18| 嘟嘟电影网在线观看| 亚洲av国产av综合av卡| 美女cb高潮喷水在线观看| 亚洲av二区三区四区| 欧美zozozo另类| 久久亚洲国产成人精品v| av一本久久久久| 午夜精品一区二区三区免费看| 国产成人91sexporn| 特大巨黑吊av在线直播| av国产免费在线观看| 特大巨黑吊av在线直播| 日韩中字成人| 极品教师在线视频| 只有这里有精品99| 在线免费观看不下载黄p国产| 国产国拍精品亚洲av在线观看| 2021少妇久久久久久久久久久| 老司机影院毛片| 久久韩国三级中文字幕| 国产精品99久久久久久久久| 青春草亚洲视频在线观看| 久久这里有精品视频免费| 99热网站在线观看| 丝瓜视频免费看黄片| eeuss影院久久| 欧美 日韩 精品 国产| 日韩中字成人| 国产欧美日韩一区二区三区在线 | 在线观看人妻少妇| 亚洲av.av天堂| 最近最新中文字幕大全电影3| 草草在线视频免费看| 国产一区有黄有色的免费视频| 日韩伦理黄色片| 九九爱精品视频在线观看| 亚洲av.av天堂| 国产高清三级在线| 自拍欧美九色日韩亚洲蝌蚪91 | 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 久久久久久久亚洲中文字幕| 高清日韩中文字幕在线| 国产大屁股一区二区在线视频| 亚洲国产av新网站| 国产成人a区在线观看| 日日撸夜夜添| 国产日韩欧美在线精品| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 国产精品国产av在线观看| 久久精品综合一区二区三区| av在线亚洲专区| 欧美日韩视频高清一区二区三区二| 亚洲欧美成人精品一区二区| 免费不卡的大黄色大毛片视频在线观看| 在线亚洲精品国产二区图片欧美 | 久久99热这里只有精品18| 99热这里只有精品一区| 婷婷色综合大香蕉| 亚洲成人一二三区av| 精品久久久久久久久亚洲| 精品99又大又爽又粗少妇毛片| 国产精品av视频在线免费观看| 亚洲精品国产av蜜桃| 菩萨蛮人人尽说江南好唐韦庄| 国产色爽女视频免费观看| 国产成人免费观看mmmm| 在线观看人妻少妇| av又黄又爽大尺度在线免费看| 国产日韩欧美在线精品| 男女边吃奶边做爰视频| 成人一区二区视频在线观看| a级毛片免费高清观看在线播放| 免费av观看视频| 一级毛片久久久久久久久女| 在线精品无人区一区二区三 | 久久人人爽av亚洲精品天堂 | www.av在线官网国产|