• <tr id="yyy80"></tr>
  • <sup id="yyy80"></sup>
  • <tfoot id="yyy80"><noscript id="yyy80"></noscript></tfoot>
  • 99热精品在线国产_美女午夜性视频免费_国产精品国产高清国产av_av欧美777_自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇_亚洲熟女精品中文字幕_www日本黄色视频网_国产精品野战在线观看 ?

    The Possibility and Method of Implanting Aesthetic Autonomy into Confucian Aesthetics: The Case of Helian Bobo

    2021-11-07 00:24:59LiuXuguang
    孔學(xué)堂 2021年3期
    關(guān)鍵詞:樂論

    Liu Xuguang

    Abstract: Chinese Confucian aesthetics takes aesthetic moralism as its priority, and yet it also presupposes aesthetic autonomy. The ancients applied a double standard to evaluate the tyrant Helian Bobo, from both the aesthetic and moral perspectives, revealing a possibility that aesthetic pleasure is independent of moral feeling. Modern Chinese scholars have been theoretically aware of aesthetic autonomy but they refuse to accept it in practice. This paper attempts to start from the “music of the rain altar” and the “realm of refreshing breeze and the bright moon” to implant aesthetic autonomy into Confucian aesthetics in order to gain independence and dignity of aesthetic perception and arts in Chinese culture and therefore be free from the traditions of aesthetic moralism and artistic utilitarianism.

    Keywords: Helian Bobo, Confucian aesthetics, aesthetic autonomy

    Helian Bobo 赫連勃勃 (r. 407–425) “was more than six feet tall, with a girdle of ten finger spans, talented in debate and beautiful in demeanor.” The ancient Chinese historian had such a rare description of the tyrant with an aesthetic attitude. In this account, aesthetics seems to break away from obscuration by politics and morality and show its independence. In ancient China, did aesthetics have its own independence? The case of Helian Bobo shows that it did, but it was concealed behind aesthetic moralism.

    The issue of aesthetic independence can also be expressed as that of aesthetic autonomy in theory. Since Kant formulated the conception of aesthetic autonomy, it has spread all over the world in two hundred years, which constitutes the basic understanding of aesthetics by modern people. What kind of theoretical response then should be made to the aesthetic thoughts of those nations that do not have aesthetic autonomy? There are only three possible responses: the first is to refuse and insist on making aesthetic activity and perception the means to achieve a goal; the second is to embrace, excavate, and enlarge the factors related to aesthetic autonomy in traditional aesthetics; the third is confrontation, adhering to their own position and forming a dialectical relationship of mutual negation and mutual regulation in the confrontation, so as to praise each others characteristics and seek compromise. The relationship between Confucian aesthetics and Western aesthetic autonomy falls into the third category.

    The Issue of Aesthetic Autonomy in Confucian Aesthetics

    [Refer to page 41 for Chinese. Similarly hereinafter]

    The history of Chinese aesthetics often uses “aesthetic moralism” to summarize the value pursuit of traditional Confucian aesthetics. That is, Confucianism always unifies aesthetics with moral judgment, moral emotion with aesthetic delight, and aesthetics with the system of ritual and music and the spirit of benevolence (ren 仁) and righteousness (yi 義). This theoretical generalization is derived from four groups of assertions in the Analects.

    Group one:

    The Master said of Shao music that it was perfectly beautiful and also perfectly good. He said of the Wu music that it was perfectly beautiful but not perfectly good. (Analects 3:25)

    In this sentence, beauty (mei 美) and goodness (shan 善) are understood as things that can be joined or separated. Here then beauty and goodness are not one but rather are separate, although they should be one.

    Zixia 子夏 (b. 507 BCE) asked, saying, “What is the meaning of the passage—‘The pretty dimples of her artful smile! The well-defined black and white of her eye! The plain ground for the colors?” The Master said, “The business of laying on the colors follows the preparation of the plain ground.” “Rites then are subsequent thing?” The Master said, “It is Zixia who can bring out my meaning. Now I can begin to talk about the Book of Songs with him.” (3:8)

    This statement places “colors” after “plain ground” and the aesthetic effect after “rites.” It shows that the aesthetic effect belongs after actual function, but does that mean that aesthetics still exists independently of actual function?

    Group two:

    The Master said, “With coarse rice to eat, with water to drink, and my bended arm for a pillow; I have still joy in the midst of these things. Riches and honors acquired by unrighteousness, are to me as a floating cloud.” (7:16)

    The Master said, “Admirable indeed was the virtue of Yan Hui 顏回 (521–490 BCE)! With a single bamboo dish of rice, a single gourd dish of drink, and living in his mean narrow lane, while others could not have endured the distress, he did not allow his joy to be affected by it. Admirable indeed was the virtue of Hui!” (6:11)

    This group refers to a kind of moral delight that transcends utilitarian satisfaction and is truly worth pursuing. The delight of Yan Hui has something in common with aesthetic delight. They are both non-utilitarian. However, from the expression that “the business of laying on the colors follows the preparation of the plain ground,” Confucius also knows that formal beauty and moral and emotional pleasure are different. They are separate, but they should be combined.

    Group three:

    Zilu 子路 (542–480 BCE) asked what constituted a complete man. The Master said, “Suppose a man with the knowledge of Zang Wuzhong 臧武仲, the freedom from covetousness of Meng Gongchuo 孟公綽, the bravery of Zhuangzi of Bian, and the varied talents of Ran Qiu 冉求 (b. 522 BCE); add to these the accomplishments of the rules of rites and music;—such a one might be reckoned a complete man.” (14:12)

    The Master said, “If a man be without the virtues proper to benevolence, what has he to do with the rites of propriety? If a man be without the virtues proper to benevolence, what has he to do with music?” (3:3)

    The Master said, “‘It is according to the rules of propriety, they say. ‘It is according to the rules of propriety, they say. Are gems and silk all that is meant by propriety? ‘It is music, they say. ‘It is music, they say. Are bells and drums all that is meant by music?” (17:11)

    This statement requires that people be educated with rites and music, and that rites and music be guided by benevolence. Rites and music are first of all used with jade, silk, bells, and drums, but they should also be attached to benevolence.

    Group four:

    “What harm is there in that?” said the Master. “Let each of you speak out your wishes.” Zeng Dian 曾點(diǎn) (b. 546 BCE) then said, “In this, the last month of spring, with the dress of the season all complete, along with five or six young men who have assumed the cap, and six or seven boys, I would wash in the Yi River, enjoy the breeze among the rain altars, and return home singing.” The Master heaved a sigh and said, “I give my approval to Dian.” (11:26)

    This dialogue encompasses a kind of amoral and non-utilitarian pleasure, which is called the delight of the “music of the rain altar” by later generations. It looks very much like the non-utilitarian, amoral, and non-conceptual spiritual delight that is the aesthetic feeling as understood by the Western theory of aesthetic autonomy.

    Beauty and goodness should coincide, aesthetic delight and moral delight should coincide, benevolence and rites and music should coincide. These constitute the three basic demands of Confucian aesthetics, but this “should” also shows that this consistency has not occurred, which means that there is a confrontation between beauty and goodness. This confrontation implies a latent presupposition that aesthetics is independent and autonomous.

    No explicit expression of this conclusion is found in the Confucian classical texts, but it can be speculated that though beauty and goodness are mentioned together, they are two distinct things. Moreover, from its pragmatic effect in the history of the Chinese language, the word mei were mainly used by the ancients to refer to what is good or fine (hao 好) and the meaning of hao overlaps with mei. Therefore, hao and shan are usually not used together in Chinese expressions to avoid redundancy. However, in the phrase jin shan jin mei 盡善盡美 (perfectly good and beautiful), mei (beautiful) and shan (good) are put together, showing that the two are semantically parallel rather than absolute synonyms, This means that calling something beautiful does not necessarily mean calling it good. At least in the Analects, the word mei has its own independence. However, later Confucian scholars adhered to aesthetic moralism in the Analects and believed that mei and shan are the same thing. For example, Xu Shen 許慎 (ca. 58–ca.147), author of The Etymological Dictionary of Characters [說文解字], first had the concept of integrating beauty and goodness and then tried to unify them in philology. Taking yang 羊 (sheep) as the bridge, he speculated that since sheep are for eating, the word mei 美, which seems like a derivative of yang, should be related to food. He then directly asserted that mei is synonymous with shan 善 (譱), both being derived from yang. As yang has the meaning of “auspiciousness,” it is inferred that shan is synonymous with yi 義 (義) and mei in meaning.

    Xu Shens literal interpretation is only the result of his theory of the synonymy of beauty and goodness, but later generations would take it as evidence for that theory. This synonymy cancels the theoretical possibility of aesthetic autonomy, but the problem is that in the Analects there exists no theory that beauty and goodness must always travel together, so the independence of beauty remains a possibility.

    In the third passage Confucius seems to treat benevolence and righteousness as the preconditions of rites and music, but do there exist any rites and music that are not consistent with benevolence and righteousness? Although Confucius does not agree with music that is not benevolent, non-benevolent rites and music do already exist! Does this mean that rites and music can be affirmed just for their beauty or refinement, regardless of moral considerations?

    The above-mentioned Confucian aesthetic reflects a theoretical contradiction. Beauty and goodness, the aesthetic value of art and its moral value, are semantically distinct, but when it comes to appraising specific cases they can be used interchangeably, which is a contradiction. This contradiction may not seem so problematic because it seldom arises in particular cases. However, there is such a particular case in Chinese history that can amplify this contradiction, such as Helian Bobo.

    Helian Bobo: A Confrontation between Aesthetic Moralism?and Aesthetic Autonomy [42]

    Theory must deal with real events. The History of the Jin Dynasty [晉書], in its “Account, the Thirtieth” [載記第三十] chapter, records the deeds of a Xiongnu descendant named Helian Bobo who established the Xia state during the Sixteen Kingdoms period (304–439). The historians who compiled the history, supervised by Fang Xuanling 房玄齡 (579–648), Chu Suiliang 褚遂良 (596–ca. 658), and Xu Jingzong 許敬宗 (592–672) in the Tang dynasty, encountered a difficult problem: the confrontation between beauty, art, and benevolence.

    “Helian Bobo was more than six feet tall, with a girdle of ten finger spans, talented in debate and beautiful in demeanor.” The introduction of the character begins with this aesthetic evaluation, which is distinctive and rare in history books. When Helian Bobo established his regime, he built and ruled numerous towns and cities, and demanded absolute refinement of craftsmanship. The account continues:

    Bobo claimed, “Now I have conquered the world, ruling all states, and thus we can name the capital city Tongwan.” Ali was particularly gifted for craftsmanship and yet he was extremely cruel and tyrannical. He had the walls built by the lime-clay injection method. He would kill the builder and bury him in the wall if ever the wall was weak enough as to allow the awl to enter an inch. For his loyalty, Bobo entrusted him with the task of construction and maintenance. Then he was commissioned to make extremely fine and sharp weaponry. Upon completion, some craftsmen would be executed: If an arrow could not pierce armor, the bow maker would be killed, and if it did pierce armor, the armor maker would be killed. Then he set to making finely tempered swords, namely black phoenix swords, called the “great Xia black phoenix swords.” . . . And he also made all kinds of mythological figures of copper and gold and displayed them in front of the palace. He killed thousands of craftsmen to ensure that his products were exquisite and beautiful.

    Killing thousands of craftsmen! This is the reason why the artifacts were exquisite, beautiful, and among the best in the world. This kind of beauty is not justified in the eyes of orthodox Confucianism. On the one hand, the text describes the ferocity and killing of Helian Bobo; on the other, it makes the following aesthetic evaluation in the final “historians comment”: “Yet he had high taste and unique character, intoxicating Emperor Wenhuan of Later Qin and moving Emperor Taizu of Song.”

    The person of Helian Bobo and the objects and buildings he supervised had high aesthetic value, but morally they deserved criticism. However, Fang Xuanling and others did not deny the former because of the latter. Their description of the image of the tyrant and the beauty of his citys artifacts is impressive. This is caused by the ambiguous attitude of Confucianism in aesthetic moralism and aesthetic autonomy. Where then is the contradiction between the two?

    First of all, aesthetic delight and moral feeling can be distinguished in experience, but they somehow overlap. Confuciuss sigh at watching pines and cypresses and the joy of listening to Shao music contain moral feeling, but they are indeed triggered by the specific objects of sensibility. Does this then mean that the “sigh of pine and cypress” and the “joy of Shao music” are aesthetic delights, or are they a moral feeling caused by the moral concept symbolized by the trees and spiritual delight aroused by the spiritual ideal contained in Shao music? In this regard, the Confucians have some insight but they do not analyze it. Instead they combine the two through analogy to virtue and philology (such as Xu Shen), enlarge them, and interpret aesthetic delight as the strengthening or guidance of moral delight, a position of aesthetic moralism. The problem is that the aesthetic value of Helian Bobo and the things he supervised is intuitive, which leads to the difficulty of aesthetic moralism: the beauty thus seen is an undeniable fact, yet it cannot be willingly affirmed.

    Second, the aesthetic judgment and moral judgment are different in essence, a fact of which Confucianism also has a clear consciousness. Aesthetic judgment is the judgment of an objects form and formal language. It is related to the delight of feeling. It may only have perceptual directness without the intervention of values. In Kants view, aesthetic judgment is aimless and non-conceptual, which is the direct judgment of the subjects inner state upon the object. Confucianism pays more attention to another phenomenon, namely that the emergence and acceptance of artistic beauty and even natural beauty are influenced by the penetration of morality into all things in human life in various ways. Therefore, in fact, aesthetic experience and appreciation judgment are more complex than Kants pure judgment of taste. In the aesthetic judgment involving moral judgment, the perceptual representation of the object not only combines with the pleasant inner state but also combines a certain value purpose. Confucian aesthetics is always the product of the combination of pure appreciation and moral connotation. In the tradition of analogy to virtue, Confucianism gives up the analysis of and emphasis on the difference between aesthetics and moral judgment, instead stressing the cooperative relationship between them. But once there is no cooperative relationship between the two, or even opposition, as for example in the case of Helian Bobo, then should we accept the independent aesthetic value of the object?

    There is another phenomenon in the judgment of taste: artistic taste may only focus on the formal language of artistic works and suspend the content of the works and moral evaluation of the artist (or not willingly conduct that moral evaluation), so as to form a conflict between artistic appreciation and moral evaluation. This conflict will lead to the moralization of artistic style and aesthetic experience, such as the evaluation of Zhao Mengfu 趙孟 (1254–1322), of whom it was written that his “calligraphy is gentle and elegant. It has inherited the genuine characteristic of Wang Xizhi 王羲之 (303–361) from afar, but its defects are delicateness and softness, lacking strong will.” “Gentleness and elegance” is an aesthetic evaluation, while “l(fā)acking strong will” is a moral evaluation. When moralism wants to deny Zhaos independent value in art, it comes up with the expression—“delicateness and softness,” which is essentially moral negation but disguised as aesthetic negation. Yet this negation is farfetched, because “gentle and elegant” is still applicable to Zhaos style! This is a paradox: “gentle and elegant” and “delicateness and softness,” which refer to almost opposite attitudes, now nevertheless refer to the same object.

    Finally, the judgment of taste has an undeniable directness and independence. It is like an unfounded intuition, without the guidance of ideas and previous norms of appreciation. Aesthetes can experience the delight given by objects themselves. This is a disaster for aesthetic moralists, because moral judgment always needs the education of moral ideas and the cultivation of moral feeling, but the directness of the experience of formal beauty does not need the intervention of ideas, which forces aesthetic moralists to fight against peoples direct experience and common sense: a tree is not beautiful, but because it has the symbolism of moral ideas, people must say that it is; or people must deny the beauty of a beautiful woman because of her bad character—this is not convincing! In the case of Helian Bobo, it is surprising that Fang Xuanling and others actually accepted the aesthetic appeal of Helian Bobo and did not deny it on account of his moral defects.

    To sum up the three points above, the conflict between aesthetic moralism and the theory of aesthetic autonomy is that aesthetic moralism does not deny the independence of aesthetic delight, but although it does also see its relationship with moral feeling, it still chooses to emphasize the connection and ignore the independence, thus causing an opposition between aesthetic delight and moral feeling in extreme cases. This conflict is magnified in the case of Helian Bobo. Historians ambivalently affirm him aesthetically but deny him morally. However, as Confucius said, “If a man be without the virtues proper to benevolence, what has he to do with the rites of propriety? If a man be without the virtues proper to benevolence, what has he to do with music?” (Analects 3:3) Orthodox Confucian scholars will not make this compromise.

    The Beauty of Weeds: The Experiential Basis for?Aesthetic Autonomy [45]

    The last sentence in the “Interpreting Rhyme-Prose” [詮賦] of Dragon-Carving and the Literary Mind [文心雕龍] reads: “In style, its ultimate achievement is beauty without excess, in diction, redundant words are shorn like weeds.” Weeds are useless, so they have to be cut off. This attitude has pervaded Chinese culture. The “Discourse on Music” [樂論] of the Xunzi declares, “Therefore, musical performances are the means of guiding enjoyment. The instruments of metal, stone, silk, and bamboo are the means to guide music, for whenever music is performed, the people sit facing it.” The “Record of Music” [樂記] in the Book of Rites clearly points out: “Virtue is the strong stem of [mans] nature, and music is the blossoming of virtue.” In the ancient Chinese tradition of musical education, morality was the purpose of music. Only when music becomes a moral sound can it obtain its own legitimacy. Aesthetic autonomy does not have sufficient legitimacy in this conceptual system. However, as shown above, the potential recognition of aesthetic autonomy and the independence of aesthetic delight make a gap between the conceptual aesthetic moralism and actual aesthetic behavior. In other words, aesthetic moralism covers up the theory of aesthetic autonomy, but the light of the latter can still pass through the former. Is there a foothold of aesthetic autonomy in Confucianism? Is it possible for weeds to be independently recognized because of their beauty?

    This does happen in practice. First of all, under aesthetic moralism, the artistic style itself has an independence of its own. For example, for ancient Chinese painters, bamboo is an object of virtue. Bamboo is hollow, jointed, bent but not broken, and has noble ambition. It is a symbol of the virtue of a gentleman. However, Zheng Xie 鄭燮 (style name Banqiao 板橋, 1693–1766) said, “When you look at bamboo in the morning in the autumn, the smoke, light, sun, shadow, and air float between sparse branches and dense leaves. My heart is full of vitality with the aspiration for painting.” It is the beauty of bamboo that triggers the painters creative impulse. The reason why he paints bamboo is not a moral motivation but an aesthetic reason. Su Shi 蘇軾 (1037–1101) once commented on Wu Daozis 吳道子 (ca. 680–ca. 758) paintings:

    When Daozi paints figures, he seems to take shadows with light, go backwards and forwards, show side-by-side, oblique, and straight lines, and multiply and divide each phase to get the natural number with perfect precision, creating new images within the rules, sending wonderful notions beyond the bold and unrestrained. He may be the only person from ancient to modern times who has sufficient capacity to create new trends.

    What is revealed is obviously a pure appreciative judgment independent of aesthetic moralism and only related to the language of form. Therefore, the concept of aesthetic moralism did not prevent the ancients from experiencing pure appreciation and judgment of art and natural objects. This indicates a possibility that the object appreciated by an aesthetic moralist will cast off moral judgment and be independent.

    Another interesting case is that of the Chinese literati playing with calamus. Acorus calamus (changpu 菖蒲) is a kind of wild grass growing on the wetland by the river. Compared with weeds, it has no particular aesthetic distinctiveness or advantages. But the literati have aestheticized it for two reasons. First, because chang 菖 is homophonic with chang 昌 (goodness), appreciating the acorus calamus has become a moral behavior. A second reason is that acorus calamus is seen to symbolize leisure in the wild and so has been used by hermits as a self-metaphor. This reason too also belongs to the category of analogy to virtue. Jiang Kui 姜夔 (Jiang Baishi 姜白石, ca. 1155–1209) said in his poem “Calamus”:

    Calamus resides by Yuelu streams with grace,

    and Xiang River flows like jade with fragrance.

    The seedlings stand strong and upright,

    retaining propriety with fragrance.

    Who says the flower bowl is too small,

    he forgets the odor lasts long.

    The mountain is small like a fist and the pond like a spoon,

    and yet its hard to fathom their depth.

    The first two lines end with grace and fragrance, which are aesthetic qualities. The second two lines contain upright and propriety, which are terms of virtue. This shows that aesthetic and virtue terms occur in parallel. Only those calami that can achieve some aesthetic effect can become scholars playthings, and each calamus can become an object analogized to virtue. Therefore, in the aesthetics of each specific object, aesthetic moralism is actually used as the grounding or background. In other words, in specific aesthetic activities, the aesthetics of the object can precede the moral evaluation of the object, and even shake free of moral evaluation. When people like a specific and pleasing experience in addition to analogy to virtue, it shows aesthetic autonomy.

    When talking about the creation of landscape paintings, Guo Xi 郭熙 (1023–1085), a painter in the Northern Song dynasty, followed the tradition of analogizing mountains and rivers to virtue. However, when presenting specific mountain scenes he wrote, “The spring mountains are calm as if smiling, the summer mountains are green as if dripping, the autumn mountains are bright and clean as if made up, and the winter mountains are bleak as if sleeping.” This is obviously an empathic aesthetic judgment based on emotional experience and does not depend on analogy to virtue. This independent aesthetic state shows that ancient peoples aesthetics did include autonomy and independence in specific aesthetic experience. The expression of weeds itself shows the relative independence of beauty. Aesthetics and aesthetic moralism are parallel, but it is a complex issue to accept this parallel in theory, or indirectly recognize aesthetic autonomy.

    Why Was Aesthetic Autonomy Not Accepted by?Modern Chinese Aesthetics? [46]

    Generally speaking, ancient Chinese critics were unwilling to admit aesthetic autonomy. If the appreciation of art and beauty is not conducive to self-cultivation and has nothing to do with merit, they reduced it to “entertainment” or “play.” This utilitarian moralism is the basic principle for the evaluation of things by Confucian-influenced scholar-officials. When this principle is specific to aesthetics, it is transformed into the fundamental issue of “the significance of aesthetics to life.” The theoretical path of Western aesthetic modernity answers the question of “cultivating a free personality.” When Kant analyzed “teleological judgment” in The Critique of Judgment, he gave such a “purpose” for aesthetic and artistic activities:

    And such must have been the age, and such the nation, that first discovered the art of reciprocal communication of ideas between the more cultured and ruder sections of the community, and how to bridge the difference between the profundity and refinement of the former and the natural simplicity and originality of the latter-in this way hitting upon that mean between higher culture and the modest worth of nature, that forms for taste also, as a sense common to all mankind, that true standard which no universal rules can supply.

    In Kants view, the ultimate purpose of aesthetic and artistic activities is to combine the ruder human nature with the cultured, and to coordinate profundity and refinement with natural simplicity and originality. The reason why aesthetic and artistic activities can achieve this goal is that they cancel the role of “concepts” in appreciative judgment. In fact, they dispel all kinds of external purposiveness for aesthetics. The subject regards “free play of the powers of representation” as the internal purposiveness of aesthetics and takes “free delight” as the essence of the sense of beauty. This kind of free play and free delight coordinates peoples profundity and refinement with their natural simplicity and originality. In Kants view, “the freedom of the imagination” in aesthetic experience is the feeling of freedom obtained after liberation from the rules imposed by knowledge. The experience of beauty is a kind of experience of freedom, and perhaps our only experience of? freedom (since Kant mentioned in his works on morality that we do not have any direct experience of “free will”), so it can be said that aesthetic experience provides an empirical confirmation of our freedom. This confirmation of freedom actually plays an intermediary role, making an analogy between the “freedom of the imagination” in aesthetic experience and the free will in moral motivation and moral action, although the two kinds of freedom are different in category. However, Kant believes that the experience of freedom in aesthetics helps us to feel and pursue free will in morality. Aesthetics has become the preparatory stage of moral non-utilitarianism because of its non-utilitarianism and non-existence. From this, he came to a conclusion that made traditional Chinese intellectuals at home and welcome: “Beauty is the symbol of morality.”

    The basis of this conclusion is the analogy and mutual promotion between aesthetic freedom and moral freedom. Will this conclusion itself discard aesthetic autonomy? It should not. After all, the pursuit of freedom and delight is the fundamental purpose of aesthetics. Whether it is conducive to the experience of free will and morality is only its incidental result rather than the ultimate purpose. Preparing for morality is one of the aesthetic meanings, but it is not the essence of aesthetics! However, the proposition that “beauty is the symbol of morality” will indeed bring conceptual conflict. It will drive people to doubt aesthetic autonomy and move toward aesthetic moralism, especially in Chinese culture with a strong tradition of aesthetic moralism.

    The acceptance of Western aesthetics in modern China began from “aesthetic education,” which is the territory of aesthetic moralism and which determines the construction of aesthetic ideas in modern Chinese aesthetics to avoid or even oppose aesthetic autonomy. For example, Cai Yuanpei 蔡元培 (1868–1940) made a concise and accurate summary of Kants aesthetics. He could accept Kants concept of pure beauty or free beauty but still turned to aesthetic moralism, writing:

    Beauty has both universality to break the barriers between my view and others views and detachment to reveal the relationship of interests. Therefore, at an important juncture exists this spirit: “Neither riches nor honors can corrupt him; neither poverty nor lowly condition can make him swerve from principle; neither threats nor force can bend him.” There is even the courage to “die to achieve benevolence” rather than to “seek survival at the cost of harming benevolence.” This kind of thing does not come about from quibbling over knowledge but from the cultivation of feelings. That is, it comes not from intellectual education but from aesthetic education.

    He seems to think that aesthetics can cultivate independent personality, and independent personality can follow moral self-discipline!

    Kant bridges between aesthetics and morality through free will, making aesthetics the preparation of morality, while Cai Yuanpei bridges between aesthetics and morality through independence of personality, making aesthetics the means of cultivating moral personality. Although both are theoretically dry, what they have in common is that they are not willing to linger upon aesthetic autonomy, hoping instead that aesthetics can guide the more valuable part of human spirit.

    More noteworthy as a theoretical reference is Mou Zongsans 牟宗三 (1909–1995) understanding of and attitude toward aesthetic autonomy. As a translator of Kants aesthetics, Mou believes that aesthetic autonomy is about the “differentiation” among aesthetics, morality, and cognition, or truth, goodness, and beauty:

    Analytically speaking, the “beauty” is the “l(fā)eisure principle” of life and the free and easy freedom of life. When people are free and easy, life begins to live, to be relaxed and free without any fear, to soar freely. But this is the leisure of subtle wisdom and meditation, which will show “abiding.” If one thus abides to the end, and there is no sense of alarm that can arise, one can fall and even indulge oneself.

    The freedom of life is indeed the fundamental purpose of aesthetic autonomy, but it cannot become the ultimate goal; otherwise it will fall into indulgence, lose wisdom, and fall into perceptual passion. In this regard, Mou Zongsan once again displays his controlling ability as the moral metaphysician and puts forward a “realm” of “truth, beauty, and goodness,” which transcends the three and reaches an unimpeded realm of their integration. Of course, this can also be understood as dissatisfaction with and abandonment of the theory of aesthetic autonomy.

    Cai Yuanpei and Mou Zongsans responses to aesthetic autonomy are representative in the history of modern Chinese aesthetics; that is, they acknowledge it in theory but do not accept it in aesthetic practice. The absence of aesthetic autonomy makes positions aesthetics as leisure and elegance, and art is thus regarded as a tool of entertainment and propaganda, which is a situation that all people who love aesthetics and art are unwilling to accept! Is it possible to implant aesthetic autonomy into China?

    Implanting Aesthetic Autonomy [50]

    The word “implant” has two connotations. One is that something that did not originally exist is created through the introduction of foreign objects; the second is that it is possible to accept foreign objects and make them survive. Just like transplanting a tree, it is not difficult to plant it. The problem is how to make it adapt to the new environment and survive. This requires appropriate conditions and appropriate implantation sites. The point at which to implant aesthetic autonomy into Chinese aesthetics lies in the “music of the rain altar” and the “realm of refreshing breeze and bright moon.”

    “I would wash in the Yi River, enjoy the breeze among the rain altars, and return home singing.” This is the ideal life as given by Zeng Dian. There is a kind of non-utilitarian spiritual delight very similar to aesthetic delight. Zeng Dians ideal of life can also be understood as a kind of “poetic existence.” In essence, this ideal of life is to pursue a non-utilitarian life and realize unity with nature. Zhu Xi 朱熹 (1130–1200) explained Zeng Dians joy as follows:

    From Zeng Dians learning, one may see the end of human desire. Heavenly principles are prevalent, filling up everything with nothing missing. Therefore when he is moving or standing still, he is most calm. And his ambition is nothing other than to inhabit where he is, to enjoy his daily life, with no intention of sacrificing himself for others at the beginning. And his mind is leisurely, straight up and down with all things in heaven and earth, and each has its own wonder, which is only revealed beyond words.

    That is to say, in daily sensory life, we can obtain a kind of non-utilitarian and transcendental spiritual delight, which is consistent with Kants aesthetic concept of modernity. As long as this delight comes from the appreciation of nature and art, it is not inconsistent to say that it is aesthetic delight. The non-utilitarian, aimless, and non-conceptual music of the rain altar determines that it is autonomous, so it can be used as the site for implanting aesthetic autonomy.

    In Zhu Xis eyes, the music of the rain altar is the same as all the things in heaven and earth, each possessing its own wonder. This is the result of subtle wisdom and subtle awakening. Therefore, obtaining the music of the rain altar is not an elegant expression or play of leisure. This “music” has independent value, which can coexist with truth and goodness. In addition, Cheng Yi 程頤 (1033–1107) also affirmed the music of the rain altar. Confucius comforted old, trusted friends and cared for the young with the heart of benevolence, so that all things could follow their nature. In Cheng Yis view, this is the essence of the music of the rain altar and the atmosphere of Yao and Shun. Transcending secular utilitarianism and making contributions to all things is the embodiment of “benevolent love,” which Kant regards as the essential characteristic of the aesthetic.

    There is also a third view:

    Thus the three Masters writing concerns rites and the will of the people. Zeng Dians ambition is expressed through drum and harp, wind and dance. The music coincides with the voice of the people. Music comes from within and rites are made without, so Confucius alone had affinity with Zeng Dian. Only music cannot be made fake, so Zeng Dian staked his ambition there.

    This is to attribute the music of the rain altar to musical education teaching—music comes within and rites are made without. In fact, it affirms the independence of music, that is, the independence of art.

    However, the “music of the rain altar” is also full of controversy in Confucianism. The moralist tradition is wary of this non-utilitarian spiritual delight. However, Zhu and Chengs interpretations are still the mainstream, and the essence of the music of the rain altar can still be interpreted as a non-utilitarian spiritual delight with metaphysical value. The affirmation of this delight can be transferred to the affirmation of aesthetics.

    In addition, as the spiritual ideal of the ancient Chinese, the “realm of refreshing breeze and bright moon” is also an implantation point of aesthetic autonomy. This spiritual realm comes from Su Shi. Boating at the Red Cliff and enjoying the moon with friends, Su Shi gained a sense of freedom as if becoming an immortal on the river and under the bright moon:

    Moreover, all things under heaven have their separate owners. If a thing does not belong to me, not a mite of it should be taken as mine. Only the refreshing breeze on the river and the bright moon over the hills, which generate in our ears a pleasant sound and in our eyes a dreamy color, are inexhaustible and can be freely enjoyed. They are an immeasurable treasure granted to us by our Creator for our common happiness.

    Its delight comes from the state of non-utilitarian freedom in the face of all things. The refreshing breeze and bright moon are publicly owned by the world. They can be taken and used at any time, freely and without obstacle. It is this sense of freedom and independence that gives people spiritual delight. This is the natural aesthetic experience of Sus own ears and eyes, and his delight is the result of perceptual intuition. This kind of pure delight with self-discipline cannot be explained by aesthetic moralism. When explaining the realm of life, Feng Youlan 馮友蘭 (1895–1990) put forward the following:

    Here is the highest human attainment in the realm of heaven and earth: One feels himself not only as part of the whole but also united with the whole. . . . The whole is the togetherness of all things, and “I” am united with the whole, so “all things are possessed by me.” This realm is called being united with heaven.

    This state of unity with heaven is similar to Su Shis line about being “as if forsaking the world and becoming winged deities, ascending to the land of immortals.” This state of everything being possessed by me reflects the transcendence of life. Aesthetics can reach the same state in the realm of refreshing breeze and bright moon, so as to surpass morality and cognition and reach the highest state of life.

    According to the influence and actual connotation of the music of the rain altar and the realm of the refreshing breeze and bright moon in the history of Chinese culture, we can infer that the understanding of aesthetics in Chinese culture itself contains the possibility of aesthetic autonomy. Among them, it encompasses the highest spiritual hopes of the West for aesthetics, as well as the basic connotation of aesthetic autonomy: a kind of universal spiritual delight without utilitarianism, conceptualization, and purpose, which is obtained through artistic activities and aesthetics—this is Chinas theory of aesthetic autonomy.

    Why must we implant this theory of aesthetic autonomy? Because without autonomy, there is no independence, and without independence, there is no dignity. In Chinese culture, with its strong tradition of moralism and utilitarianism, without the support of aesthetic autonomy and artistic autonomy, art and aesthetics lack independent value. Although they may be endowed with many social functions, they have no dignity! Only by recognizing the autonomy of aesthetics and art can we recognize the transcendence of aesthetics and the creativity of art. Recognizing aesthetic autonomy means freeing ourselves from the Helian dilemma. Even if there are evil, unworthy, and worthless parts in the subject, aesthetics should not be canceled. Aesthetics has its own autonomy and has nothing to do with good and evil.

    Bibliography of Cited Translations

    Knoblock, John, trans. Xunzi [荀子] (Chinese–English version). 2 vols. Library of Chinese Classics [大中華文庫]. Changsha: Hunan Peoples Publishing House; Beijing: Foreign Languages Press, 1999.

    Legge, James, trans. Confucian Analects. Vol. 1, The Chinese Classics. Taipei: SMC Publishing Inc., 1991.

    ———. Liji. https://ctext.org/liji/ens, accessed August 22, 2021.

    Xie, Baikui 謝百魁, trans. A Collection of Chinese Ancient Prose Writings [中國歷代散文譯萃]. 2 vols. Beijing: China Translation & Publishing Corporation, 2014.

    Yang, Guobin 楊國斌, trans. Dragon-Carving and the Literary Mind [文心雕龍] (Chinese–English version). 2 vols. Library of Chinese Classics. Beijing: Foreign Language Teaching and Research Press, 2003.

    Translated by Zhu Yuan

    猜你喜歡
    樂論
    略論歐陽修的樂論美學(xué)思想
    百花(2024年10期)2024-12-11 00:00:00
    荀子的音樂美學(xué)思想探析
    從班固的禮樂觀看漢代樂論思想的重建——以《漢書·禮樂志》為例
    直筆建安骨 德勇展胸懷
    ——評蘇夏先生樂論文章 蒲方
    人民音樂(2020年8期)2020-10-28 09:03:12
    “道志”“樂心”
    北方音樂(2019年15期)2019-10-09 03:49:54
    簡論嵇康《聲無哀樂論》思想
    荀子《樂論》中的中國傳統(tǒng)美學(xué)思想
    薩班《樂論》所體現(xiàn)的音樂知識體系和審美特征研究
    西藏研究(2017年5期)2018-01-30 08:39:22
    薩班《樂論》再翻譯的必要性
    黃庭堅(jiān)詩歌形式觀的再探討
    2021天堂中文幕一二区在线观| 免费人成在线观看视频色| 亚洲自偷自拍三级| 在线播放无遮挡| 精品久久久久久久人妻蜜臀av| 高清欧美精品videossex| 亚洲国产精品成人综合色| 日韩精品青青久久久久久| 国产伦在线观看视频一区| 熟妇人妻不卡中文字幕| 欧美日韩国产mv在线观看视频 | 搡老妇女老女人老熟妇| 热99在线观看视频| 天堂中文最新版在线下载 | 99久久精品国产国产毛片| 男女边吃奶边做爰视频| 91aial.com中文字幕在线观看| 欧美不卡视频在线免费观看| 国产成人a区在线观看| 成年人午夜在线观看视频 | 亚洲高清免费不卡视频| 超碰av人人做人人爽久久| 精品人妻偷拍中文字幕| 99热这里只有是精品50| 一级二级三级毛片免费看| 国产一区亚洲一区在线观看| 精品久久久久久久久亚洲| 国产色爽女视频免费观看| 插阴视频在线观看视频| 亚洲精品乱久久久久久| 少妇被粗大猛烈的视频| 亚洲精品aⅴ在线观看| 99热全是精品| 久久99热这里只有精品18| .国产精品久久| 免费av不卡在线播放| 99久久九九国产精品国产免费| 国内精品一区二区在线观看| a级毛片免费高清观看在线播放| 人体艺术视频欧美日本| 国产伦在线观看视频一区| 免费看日本二区| 亚洲精品中文字幕在线视频 | 高清日韩中文字幕在线| 亚洲欧美精品自产自拍| 国产熟女欧美一区二区| 91精品国产九色| 一级黄片播放器| 最近的中文字幕免费完整| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区| 成人无遮挡网站| 国产精品综合久久久久久久免费| 老女人水多毛片| 老女人水多毛片| 夜夜爽夜夜爽视频| av卡一久久| 国产精品一及| 高清午夜精品一区二区三区| 十八禁网站网址无遮挡 | 日本黄色片子视频| 国产精品久久久久久精品电影小说 | 国产永久视频网站| 天天一区二区日本电影三级| 日本一本二区三区精品| 久久精品久久久久久久性| 色哟哟·www| 五月伊人婷婷丁香| 一区二区三区高清视频在线| 白带黄色成豆腐渣| 国产在线男女| 97精品久久久久久久久久精品| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜爱| 亚洲va在线va天堂va国产| 春色校园在线视频观看| 午夜老司机福利剧场| 国国产精品蜜臀av免费| 一区二区三区高清视频在线| 高清午夜精品一区二区三区| 中文字幕av成人在线电影| 日本色播在线视频| 99久久中文字幕三级久久日本| 99久久精品热视频| 国产真实伦视频高清在线观看| av.在线天堂| 国产黄片美女视频| 色网站视频免费| 纵有疾风起免费观看全集完整版 | 亚洲怡红院男人天堂| 亚洲精品乱码久久久久久按摩| 又爽又黄无遮挡网站| 午夜免费激情av| 欧美成人一区二区免费高清观看| 成人无遮挡网站| 国产麻豆成人av免费视频| 免费在线观看成人毛片| 国产 亚洲一区二区三区 | 欧美日韩一区二区视频在线观看视频在线 | 麻豆久久精品国产亚洲av| 亚洲国产高清在线一区二区三| 国产爱豆传媒在线观看| 亚洲无线观看免费| 高清毛片免费看| 秋霞伦理黄片| 免费观看精品视频网站| 极品少妇高潮喷水抽搐| 真实男女啪啪啪动态图| 青春草视频在线免费观看| 91精品一卡2卡3卡4卡| 日本熟妇午夜| 99久久精品一区二区三区| 最近2019中文字幕mv第一页| 中文乱码字字幕精品一区二区三区 | 国模一区二区三区四区视频| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 久久精品久久久久久噜噜老黄| 亚洲精品乱码久久久久久按摩| 1000部很黄的大片| 亚洲欧美精品自产自拍| 成年女人看的毛片在线观看| 九九在线视频观看精品| 少妇高潮的动态图| 成人午夜精彩视频在线观看| 三级男女做爰猛烈吃奶摸视频| 永久网站在线| 日本免费在线观看一区| 国产成人freesex在线| kizo精华| 80岁老熟妇乱子伦牲交| 直男gayav资源| 亚洲精品第二区| 国产v大片淫在线免费观看| 精品亚洲乱码少妇综合久久| 少妇熟女欧美另类| 午夜老司机福利剧场| or卡值多少钱| 国产高清有码在线观看视频| 男插女下体视频免费在线播放| 天堂俺去俺来也www色官网 | 亚洲美女搞黄在线观看| 日韩视频在线欧美| 91精品一卡2卡3卡4卡| 插逼视频在线观看| 街头女战士在线观看网站| 亚洲欧美日韩无卡精品| 欧美不卡视频在线免费观看| 特级一级黄色大片| 亚洲色图av天堂| 国产精品一区二区性色av| 久久久午夜欧美精品| 菩萨蛮人人尽说江南好唐韦庄| 天堂√8在线中文| 国产av不卡久久| 日韩制服骚丝袜av| 国产 亚洲一区二区三区 | 一级毛片 在线播放| 亚洲av福利一区| 69人妻影院| 日韩亚洲欧美综合| 久久精品国产亚洲网站| 成人鲁丝片一二三区免费| 蜜桃亚洲精品一区二区三区| 久久久久久久久久久丰满| 免费观看精品视频网站| 亚洲性久久影院| 免费看光身美女| 人妻夜夜爽99麻豆av| 国产三级在线视频| 精品一区二区免费观看| www.色视频.com| 国产午夜精品久久久久久一区二区三区| 91午夜精品亚洲一区二区三区| 又大又黄又爽视频免费| 国产欧美另类精品又又久久亚洲欧美| 成人特级av手机在线观看| av免费在线看不卡| 亚洲av免费在线观看| 亚洲精品色激情综合| 亚洲欧美日韩卡通动漫| 大香蕉97超碰在线| 三级国产精品片| 晚上一个人看的免费电影| 九九爱精品视频在线观看| 99热这里只有是精品50| 免费看不卡的av| 久久久久久久久久久免费av| 大香蕉久久网| av.在线天堂| 久久精品人妻少妇| 2021天堂中文幕一二区在线观| 国产午夜精品久久久久久一区二区三区| 国产一区二区三区av在线| 黄片wwwwww| 日韩制服骚丝袜av| 亚洲精品色激情综合| 97在线视频观看| 综合色丁香网| 日韩av在线大香蕉| 欧美日韩国产mv在线观看视频 | 免费看不卡的av| 天天一区二区日本电影三级| 女人久久www免费人成看片| 夫妻性生交免费视频一级片| 精品国产一区二区三区久久久樱花 | 黄色配什么色好看| 免费看a级黄色片| 亚洲熟妇中文字幕五十中出| 国产精品一及| 最新中文字幕久久久久| 国产成人福利小说| 校园人妻丝袜中文字幕| 非洲黑人性xxxx精品又粗又长| 国产成人精品一,二区| 亚洲av二区三区四区| 国产三级在线视频| 亚洲欧美成人综合另类久久久| 日本wwww免费看| 69人妻影院| 日本黄色片子视频| 免费看不卡的av| 精品人妻偷拍中文字幕| 3wmmmm亚洲av在线观看| 街头女战士在线观看网站| 免费观看a级毛片全部| 五月伊人婷婷丁香| 亚洲av电影在线观看一区二区三区 | 91av网一区二区| 深爱激情五月婷婷| 成年人午夜在线观看视频 | 亚洲成人一二三区av| 老师上课跳d突然被开到最大视频| 日韩在线高清观看一区二区三区| 老司机影院毛片| 街头女战士在线观看网站| 国产一区二区亚洲精品在线观看| 精品欧美国产一区二区三| 又黄又爽又刺激的免费视频.| 成人亚洲精品一区在线观看 | 美女国产视频在线观看| 淫秽高清视频在线观看| 日韩欧美精品免费久久| 国产一级毛片在线| 亚洲人成网站在线观看播放| 麻豆久久精品国产亚洲av| 久久久成人免费电影| 免费av毛片视频| 免费电影在线观看免费观看| 久久久精品欧美日韩精品| 久久久久精品性色| 十八禁国产超污无遮挡网站| 国产精品一区二区三区四区免费观看| 91狼人影院| 99视频精品全部免费 在线| 国产高潮美女av| 亚洲av成人精品一二三区| 激情五月婷婷亚洲| 免费观看无遮挡的男女| 亚洲国产色片| 久久精品国产亚洲av天美| 人人妻人人看人人澡| 只有这里有精品99| eeuss影院久久| 日本爱情动作片www.在线观看| 成人av在线播放网站| 免费看日本二区| 日韩视频在线欧美| 免费大片黄手机在线观看| 身体一侧抽搐| 国产不卡一卡二| 亚洲国产欧美人成| 六月丁香七月| 一级黄片播放器| 在线观看人妻少妇| 欧美激情国产日韩精品一区| 亚洲第一区二区三区不卡| 91av网一区二区| 精品久久久久久久久av| 少妇猛男粗大的猛烈进出视频 | 欧美激情在线99| 成人性生交大片免费视频hd| 国产91av在线免费观看| 国产白丝娇喘喷水9色精品| 黄片wwwwww| 我要看日韩黄色一级片| 插阴视频在线观看视频| 女人被狂操c到高潮| 联通29元200g的流量卡| 久久亚洲国产成人精品v| ponron亚洲| 国产av不卡久久| 人妻少妇偷人精品九色| 午夜免费观看性视频| 免费观看在线日韩| 国产av在哪里看| 日韩制服骚丝袜av| 国产精品精品国产色婷婷| 国产精品国产三级国产专区5o| 少妇的逼水好多| 国产极品天堂在线| 日韩成人av中文字幕在线观看| 国产精品久久久久久久久免| 成人午夜精彩视频在线观看| 一区二区三区高清视频在线| 亚洲国产欧美在线一区| 亚洲欧美清纯卡通| 十八禁国产超污无遮挡网站| 高清午夜精品一区二区三区| 日韩精品有码人妻一区| 午夜激情久久久久久久| 少妇裸体淫交视频免费看高清| 18禁在线播放成人免费| 亚洲国产精品成人久久小说| 秋霞伦理黄片| 欧美日韩在线观看h| 国精品久久久久久国模美| 女的被弄到高潮叫床怎么办| 亚洲av在线观看美女高潮| 日韩在线高清观看一区二区三区| av网站免费在线观看视频 | 国产一区亚洲一区在线观看| 久久韩国三级中文字幕| 99久久人妻综合| 国内精品美女久久久久久| 色哟哟·www| 亚洲精品456在线播放app| 久久久久久久久久久免费av| 亚洲精品日韩av片在线观看| 嫩草影院精品99| a级毛色黄片| 十八禁网站网址无遮挡 | 中文天堂在线官网| 一级毛片电影观看| 日本黄色片子视频| 亚洲最大成人中文| 国产一区二区三区av在线| 亚洲国产欧美在线一区| 两个人视频免费观看高清| 免费看日本二区| 人人妻人人澡人人爽人人夜夜 | 天美传媒精品一区二区| 欧美极品一区二区三区四区| 少妇的逼水好多| 寂寞人妻少妇视频99o| 高清日韩中文字幕在线| 能在线免费看毛片的网站| 熟妇人妻不卡中文字幕| 少妇高潮的动态图| 男人舔女人下体高潮全视频| 亚洲欧美日韩卡通动漫| 亚洲av不卡在线观看| 国产日韩欧美在线精品| 天天一区二区日本电影三级| 99热网站在线观看| 熟女人妻精品中文字幕| 99久久精品一区二区三区| av.在线天堂| 亚洲一级一片aⅴ在线观看| 午夜福利在线观看吧| 亚洲美女搞黄在线观看| 少妇高潮的动态图| eeuss影院久久| 亚洲欧美日韩卡通动漫| 国产精品蜜桃在线观看| 不卡视频在线观看欧美| 深夜a级毛片| 亚洲av一区综合| 久久99热6这里只有精品| 亚洲无线观看免费| 街头女战士在线观看网站| 成人漫画全彩无遮挡| 99热这里只有是精品在线观看| 91精品一卡2卡3卡4卡| 国产真实伦视频高清在线观看| 精品一区在线观看国产| 最近2019中文字幕mv第一页| 欧美人与善性xxx| 亚洲18禁久久av| 蜜桃亚洲精品一区二区三区| 精品不卡国产一区二区三区| 国产视频首页在线观看| 午夜福利成人在线免费观看| 你懂的网址亚洲精品在线观看| 久久亚洲国产成人精品v| 91久久精品电影网| 淫秽高清视频在线观看| 亚洲一区高清亚洲精品| 欧美日韩综合久久久久久| 搡老乐熟女国产| 丝瓜视频免费看黄片| 国产一级毛片七仙女欲春2| 欧美性感艳星| 国产 一区 欧美 日韩| 91久久精品电影网| 丰满乱子伦码专区| 91精品国产九色| 欧美精品一区二区大全| 视频中文字幕在线观看| 日韩视频在线欧美| 哪个播放器可以免费观看大片| 在现免费观看毛片| 麻豆成人av视频| 草草在线视频免费看| 18禁裸乳无遮挡免费网站照片| 亚洲美女搞黄在线观看| 插逼视频在线观看| 国产一区二区亚洲精品在线观看| 免费看日本二区| av在线蜜桃| 精品久久久精品久久久| 久久精品国产亚洲av涩爱| 少妇的逼好多水| 蜜桃久久精品国产亚洲av| 永久免费av网站大全| 丰满乱子伦码专区| 亚洲av在线观看美女高潮| 汤姆久久久久久久影院中文字幕 | 精品欧美国产一区二区三| 精品亚洲乱码少妇综合久久| 国产精品一区二区性色av| 乱人视频在线观看| 亚洲精品乱码久久久v下载方式| 成人毛片60女人毛片免费| 日韩成人av中文字幕在线观看| 国产乱人偷精品视频| freevideosex欧美| 一本久久精品| 欧美人与善性xxx| 精品久久久久久久久av| 99久久人妻综合| 午夜福利在线在线| 美女内射精品一级片tv| 免费少妇av软件| 亚洲乱码一区二区免费版| 日韩欧美精品免费久久| 99re6热这里在线精品视频| 久久久久久伊人网av| 国产精品美女特级片免费视频播放器| 97超碰精品成人国产| 国产精品av视频在线免费观看| 亚洲欧美日韩卡通动漫| 国产久久久一区二区三区| 久久精品人妻少妇| 国产亚洲午夜精品一区二区久久 | 国产免费视频播放在线视频 | 久久国产乱子免费精品| 久久久久网色| 看免费成人av毛片| 又粗又硬又长又爽又黄的视频| 女的被弄到高潮叫床怎么办| 国产女主播在线喷水免费视频网站 | 亚洲av电影在线观看一区二区三区 | 国产精品国产三级国产av玫瑰| 男人爽女人下面视频在线观看| 成人欧美大片| 国产一区二区三区av在线| 亚洲欧美日韩卡通动漫| 乱码一卡2卡4卡精品| 国产成人精品久久久久久| 亚洲国产欧美人成| 非洲黑人性xxxx精品又粗又长| 国产成人freesex在线| 日日撸夜夜添| 51国产日韩欧美| 免费看不卡的av| 91aial.com中文字幕在线观看| 深爱激情五月婷婷| 如何舔出高潮| 国产精品一区二区在线观看99 | 美女国产视频在线观看| 亚洲精品国产av成人精品| 可以在线观看毛片的网站| 我的老师免费观看完整版| a级毛片免费高清观看在线播放| 国产美女午夜福利| 国产成人freesex在线| 七月丁香在线播放| 成人性生交大片免费视频hd| 欧美激情国产日韩精品一区| xxx大片免费视频| 成年av动漫网址| 日产精品乱码卡一卡2卡三| 一区二区三区乱码不卡18| 国产伦理片在线播放av一区| 久久久久精品久久久久真实原创| 大香蕉97超碰在线| av专区在线播放| 亚洲自拍偷在线| 一本久久精品| 久久久久久久久久成人| 99久久中文字幕三级久久日本| 亚洲成人一二三区av| 国产高潮美女av| 性插视频无遮挡在线免费观看| 小蜜桃在线观看免费完整版高清| 婷婷六月久久综合丁香| 狂野欧美白嫩少妇大欣赏| 国产成人精品福利久久| 高清av免费在线| 午夜精品国产一区二区电影 | 韩国av在线不卡| 麻豆久久精品国产亚洲av| 少妇猛男粗大的猛烈进出视频 | 亚洲在线观看片| 日韩伦理黄色片| 韩国av在线不卡| 麻豆久久精品国产亚洲av| 能在线免费看毛片的网站| 岛国毛片在线播放| 天美传媒精品一区二区| 国产午夜精品一二区理论片| 国产精品国产三级国产av玫瑰| 三级国产精品片| 日本-黄色视频高清免费观看| 日日干狠狠操夜夜爽| 97超碰精品成人国产| 九色成人免费人妻av| 直男gayav资源| 亚洲国产精品sss在线观看| 欧美xxxx性猛交bbbb| 在线a可以看的网站| 嫩草影院入口| 免费看光身美女| 亚洲av一区综合| 国产成人一区二区在线| 国产精品精品国产色婷婷| 人人妻人人看人人澡| 激情五月婷婷亚洲| 青春草视频在线免费观看| 99久久精品热视频| 18禁动态无遮挡网站| 国产精品福利在线免费观看| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区| 22中文网久久字幕| 99久久精品国产国产毛片| 成人亚洲欧美一区二区av| 91在线精品国自产拍蜜月| 国产成人一区二区在线| 一级二级三级毛片免费看| 久久久欧美国产精品| 国产亚洲午夜精品一区二区久久 | 亚洲精品一区蜜桃| 日本午夜av视频| 99久国产av精品| 97人妻精品一区二区三区麻豆| 成人毛片60女人毛片免费| or卡值多少钱| 91精品一卡2卡3卡4卡| 国产亚洲最大av| 秋霞伦理黄片| 久久久久久久午夜电影| 亚洲丝袜综合中文字幕| 一边亲一边摸免费视频| 午夜精品一区二区三区免费看| 亚洲av.av天堂| 内地一区二区视频在线| av免费观看日本| 天堂俺去俺来也www色官网 | 日韩制服骚丝袜av| 中文字幕制服av| 精华霜和精华液先用哪个| 成人鲁丝片一二三区免费| 日产精品乱码卡一卡2卡三| 久久精品夜色国产| 国产永久视频网站| 国产精品一区www在线观看| 午夜福利在线观看免费完整高清在| 欧美成人一区二区免费高清观看| 欧美激情久久久久久爽电影| 天美传媒精品一区二区| 欧美人与善性xxx| 一级毛片久久久久久久久女| 特级一级黄色大片| 天美传媒精品一区二区| 天天一区二区日本电影三级| 免费看美女性在线毛片视频| 中文字幕av在线有码专区| 日本猛色少妇xxxxx猛交久久| 久久久久久久亚洲中文字幕| 久久99热这里只有精品18| 蜜桃久久精品国产亚洲av| 日韩伦理黄色片| 特大巨黑吊av在线直播| 国产真实伦视频高清在线观看| 99热这里只有是精品在线观看| 亚洲av中文av极速乱| 亚洲人与动物交配视频| 国产爱豆传媒在线观看| 精品一区二区三区视频在线| 国产精品一区二区性色av| 日本欧美国产在线视频| 国产午夜福利久久久久久| 午夜福利视频1000在线观看| 一级毛片黄色毛片免费观看视频| 亚洲国产最新在线播放| 精品国产一区二区三区久久久樱花 | 床上黄色一级片| 日韩电影二区| 亚洲欧洲日产国产| 赤兔流量卡办理| 狂野欧美激情性xxxx在线观看| 午夜免费男女啪啪视频观看| 淫秽高清视频在线观看| 免费看不卡的av| 成人漫画全彩无遮挡| 国产伦在线观看视频一区| 少妇裸体淫交视频免费看高清| 欧美激情国产日韩精品一区| 视频中文字幕在线观看| 日韩国内少妇激情av| av在线播放精品| 国产精品.久久久| 一区二区三区免费毛片| 99视频精品全部免费 在线| 高清欧美精品videossex| 亚洲av日韩在线播放| 国产精品一区www在线观看|