• <tr id="yyy80"></tr>
  • <sup id="yyy80"></sup>
  • <tfoot id="yyy80"><noscript id="yyy80"></noscript></tfoot>
  • 99热精品在线国产_美女午夜性视频免费_国产精品国产高清国产av_av欧美777_自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇_亚洲熟女精品中文字幕_www日本黄色视频网_国产精品野战在线观看 ?

    Quine on the Ground of Logical Truths*

    2020-01-03 06:33:46CongWangWenfangWang
    邏輯學(xué)研究 2019年6期

    Cong Wang Wen-fang Wang

    Abstract.It is well known that Quine objected to the linguistic doctrine of logical truths according to which logical truths are true purely by virtue of the language,or true purely by virtue of the meanings of logical words occurring in them.Quine’s reasons for rejecting the linguistic doctrine of logical truths are various and seemingly powerful.However,a closer look at Quine’s arguments shows that,the authors believe,they are at most inconclusive.In this paper,the authors scrutinize several arguments given by Quine in his work and endeavor to point out the weakness of these arguments.The authors conclude that the linguistic doctrine of logical truths,and hence the analytic/synthetic distinction,is not undermined by Quine’s attacks.

    It is well known that Quine objected to the linguistic doctrine of logical truths(“LD”henceforth)according to which logical truths are“true purely by virtue of the language”or true purely by virtue of the meanings of logical words occurring in them.1Quine([12],pp.95-96)characterized what we call“LD”here or what he called“the linguistic theory of logical truth”there as the doctrine that logical truths are“true purely by virtue of the language”or”true by virtue purely of its grammatical structure.”Carnap([3],p.916)on the other hand,characterized logical truths in several different ways:sometimes as truths based on“l(fā)inguistic fiat”,sometimes as true by“l(fā)inguistic conventions”,and sometimes as truths“based on meanings”.(He took the last characterization to be better than the previous two in that the previous two are“psychologically unhelpful”.)All these characterizations are,of course,very vague and arguably non-equivalent,and therefore should be avoided if possible.The alternative characterization of LD as the doctrine that logical truths are true purely by virtue of the meanings of logical words occurring in them is due to Hellman ([4],p.190).This characterization is obviously much more precise than the previous ones and has somehow become standard.However,following Hellman and Boghossian,we will further introduce two ways of explicating this alternative characterization in the paragraph next to the next one,and therefore will not take this formulation of LD as final.LD is a doctrine that was developed by the Vienna Circle on the basis of Wittgenstein’s idea and was officially maintained by Carnap for his whole life.Quine’s reasons to reject LD are various and seemingly powerful;however,a closer look at these arguments will show that,we believe,they are at most inconclusive.In what follows,we will scrutinize several arguments given by Quine in his work and try to point out the weakness of these arguments.We will conclude that LD,and hence the analytic/synthetic distinction,is not undermined by Quine’s attacks.Before we start,however,let us make a couple of preliminary remarks.

    First,to foster the following discussion,we shall quickly agree with Quine([9],p.110)that logical truths are adequately characterized as“those true sentences which involve only logical wordsessentially”,whereas what count as“l(fā)ogical words”is simply determined by a given list that,let us assume,includes“not”,“or”,“all”,“is identical with”and so on.More explicitly,what this characterization means is that,given a list of logical words,the so-called“l(fā)ogical truths”can be identified as those true sentences such that“any [non-logical]words [occurring in them]… can be varied at will without engendering falsity.”Thus,“John is identical with John”and“John is a man or John is not a man”are examples of logical truths according to this characterization,for,if we replace“John”and/or“is a man”uniformly with any grammatically admissible expressions we like,the results will be sentences that have the same truth-value,i.e.,truth,as these two.Note that what this characterization intends to do is simply to draw the boundary between logical truths and non-logical ones;it says nothing about how logical truths are supposed to be known or about how their truth is grounded.

    To be sure,the characterization of LD as the doctrine that logical truths are true purely by virtue of the meanings of the logical words occurring in them is just a long-winded way to say the simpler thing that logical truths are analytical truths.Understood in this way,it is not surprising that Quine objected to LD,given his famous denouncement of the traditional analytic/synthetic distinction in“Tow Dogmas of Empiricism”([11]).As a matter of fact,however,Quine had launched a series of relentless attacks on LD ever since 1936:first in his article“Truth by Convention”([10]),then in the article“Carnap and Logical Truth”([9]),and finally in the bookPhilosophy of Logic([12]).Quine’s attacks on LD in these writings are,however,out of focus,and this is where our second remark is about.As many philosophers(e.g.,Hellman([4])and Boghossian([2]))have pointed out,Quine’s discursive attacks on the analyticity of logical truths can be and should be sorted into two kinds:those against the epistemic claim that logical truths area prioriknowable and those against the metaphysical claim that logical truths are made true by linguistic conventions.2The epistemic claim and the metaphysical claim are,roughly,Hellman’s([4])LD(II)and LD(III).Boghssian ([2])called these claims“epistemic analyticity”and“metaphysical analyticity”separately,but we find this terminology misleading.Carnap ([3],p.916)seemed to have the epistemic claim in mind when he said that understanding logical truths“is a sufficient basis for the determination of their truth.”In other words,LD can be taken either as an epistemic doctrine that mere grasp of the meanings of the logical words contained in a logical truth suffices for one to be justified in holding the sentence true,or as a metaphysical doctrine that logical truths owe their truth completely to the meanings of logical words therein.We should,therefore,be very careful about which doctrine or version of LD is the target of a specific argument of Quine,for a powerful argument against one of these two versions of LD may not be so against the other.3Boghossian([2])thinks that the epistemic version of LD is defensible but the metaphysical version is not,whereas Hellman ([4])thinks that both LD(II)and LD(III)are defensible.We are inclined to agree with Hellman,for we think that Quine’s attacks hurt neither of them.

    With these preliminary remarks in mind,let us proceed to scrutinize Quine’s arguments against LD.We will,however,put our focus more on the two arguments of Quine given in hisPhilosophy of Logic,for it seems to us that philosophers have not paid enough attention to them yet.

    1 Quine’s Arguments against LD in Philosophy of Logic(PL)

    As we see it,there are at least two new arguments against LD in PL that were not even hinted by Quine in his early writings.The first of these ([12],pp.95-96)aims at what appears to be a common presupposition of both versions of LD,namely,the presupposition that a distinction between logical words and non-logical words can somehow be made,and appeals to the notion of an immanent distinction.Here is how Quine put the argument:

    … [T]he very distinction between grammar and lexicon is immanent,and admits of alternative adjustments even in the analysis of one and the same language.As this distinction varies,the distinction between logical truth and other truth varies with it.Insofar,the demarcation of logical truth rests on the whim of the descriptive grammarian.Now one would hesitate to let a sentence vacillate between being true purely by virtue of the language and being true partly by virtue of the nature of the world,according as the grammarian chooses to describe our already existing language in one or other of two permissible ways.

    The argument contained in this paragraph,we think,can be faithfully reformulated as the following one(call this argument“PLAr1”):

    (1)The distinction between logical words and non-logical words4When Quine([12],p.95)wrote“the distinction between grammar and lexicon”he meant the distinction between grammatical particles and lexicon.This is a distinction often made by grammarians.The parallel distinction in logic is,we take it,the distinction between logical words such as“or”and“is identical with”and non-logical words such as“John”and“is a man”.is immanent and admits of alternative adjustments.

    (2)If (1)is true,then the distinction between logical truths and other truths will vary in accordance with how the grammarian chooses their logical words.

    (3)If (1),(2)and LD are all true,then what counts as true purely by virtue of the language will vary in accordance with how the grammarian chooses their logical words.

    (4)It would be absurd to say that what counts as true purely by virtue of the language will vary in accordance with how the grammarian chooses their logical words.

    (5)Therefore,LD is not true.

    Put in this way,PLAr1 is no doubt a valid argument,but it is also clear that the advocate of LD will not accept all of its premises.Which premise or premises of PLAr1 can be resisted? We suppose that the advocate of LD should yield to(2)and(4)5We think that(4)is obvious:given a fixed language,one should not allow the distinction between logical and non-logical truths and hence the distinction between analytic and synthetic truths to vary in accordance with how the grammarian chooses logical words.To see the plausibility of(2),readers need only think of the sentence“John is a man or John is not a man”as an example.If we take“or”and“not”to be logical words,it will be a logical truth in the Quinean sense,i.e.,it will remain true no matter how the non-logical words in it are substituted for in a uniform way.However,if we decide to take“John”,“is a man”and“not”to be logical words,it will no more remain true when we substitute“and”for“or”,and hence no more be a logical truth.,but we also think that s/he should cast some doubt on(1)and directly reject(3).Let us explain the problem of(1)first.Note that the notion of an immanent distinction(or an immanent notion in general)mentioned in(1)of PLAr1 is the notion of a grammatical distinction(or a grammatical notion in general)that is defined for a particular language([12],p.19).By contrast,a transcendent distinction(or a transcendent notion in general)is a grammatical distinction(or a grammatical notion in general)that is directed to languages generally.Now,not only did Quine believe that the distinctionhemade between logical words and non-logical words by a list was immanent(obviously it is),he also believed that no transcendent distinction between them is defensible.As a matter of fact,this latter belief is what really is required for the conclusion of PLAr1;for,if the distinction at issue can be made successfully in a transcendent way,we can then simply adopt that transcendent definition and thereby reject(1).But why did Quine think that no transcendent distinction at issue is defensible? As far as we can see,Quine considered in PL only one unsuccessful attempt to define the distinction between logical words and non-logical words in a transcendent way;6The transcendent attempt Quine considered in PL classified lexicon into categories and defined the category of an expression to be the set of all the expressions that are interchangeable with it salva congruitate.([12],pp.18-19)after arguing that it was not satisfactory,he then concluded that“we have no defensible transcendent notion of [logical words]or lexicon”([12],p.60).But this conclusion is certainly too hasty.

    In order to cast more doubt on (1),we will briefly sketch here a transcendent way of defining the distinction between logical words and non-logical words that appears to us to be more promising than the one considered by Quine in PL.(We will suggest another one,one that appeals to“occur essentially”,later on in this section.)According to many philosophers,what makes logic so unique is that it is not about anything in particular.So,it is natural to think of logical words in any language as those expressions in that language that are“topic-neutral”.However,we need to sharpen the notion of“topic-neutrality”involved here not only to make the demarcation more precise but also to make sure that the notion so defined will finally turn out to be a transcendent one.Both tasks,it seems to many philosophers(e.g.,Mostowski([8]),Scott([13]),McCarthy([6]),Tarski([16]),van Benthem([1]),Sher([14]),and McGee([7])),can be accomplished by defining a logical word as an expression thatremains invariant in extension under arbitrary permutations of any domain.For details of this kind of definitions,readers are referred to [5].7A problem about the permutation invariance criterion is that it applies only to extensional operators and truth-functional connectives but not to operators in various kinds of intensional logics or hyperintensional ones.Though the invariance criterion can be extended in a natural way to intensional operators and thereby shows that some intensional operators,such as modal operators of S5,are logical,it is still not clear how this criterion can be further extended.Besides,it is always debatable whether judgments by applying this criterion to other operators are always correct.We thank an anonymous reviewer to bring up this issue and think that this issue,though important,has no bite to our moderate conclusion.More to the point:the definition we give several paragraphs later is also a transcendent one and it seems to us that it is more inclusive than this permutation invariance criterion.Notice that,defined in this way,the distinction between logical words and non-logical ones in a language is a transcendent one,one that applicable to languages in general.Now,ifthis particular(or any other)transcendent way of distinguishing logical words from non-logical ones in a language is defensible,we can then reject the premise (1)of PLAr1.We do not mean to suggest that this particular way of defining the distinction at issueisespecially satisfactory;our point is simply that one should not rashly accept Quine’s premise(1)of PLAr1 before all attempts to make a transcendent distinction between logical words and non-logical ones are shown to fail their tasks.

    (1)of PLAr1 is therefore dubious.Yet,we think that the advocate of LD can even go a step further to directly reject (3)of that argument.(3)of PLAr1 implies that if the distinction between logical words(or logical truths)and non-logical words(or non-logical truths)can only be immanent and admits of alternative adjustments,then what counts as true purely by virtue of the language will become a relative matter if LD is true.This implication seems to us to be completely objectionable.Before we explain why it is so,however,let us pause for a while and think about this question:suppose the advocate of LD agrees that the distinction between logical and non-logical words and hence the distinction between logical and non-logical truths can only be immanent and admits of alternative adjustments,how would s/he formulate LD?Of course it would be foolish for him or her to formulate it as“all logical truths are true purely by virtue of the meanings of the logical words”,because what counts as logical words or truths in this case will vary according to how the grammarian chooses logical words.A more appropriate way to formulate his or her doctrine,given that s/he accepts that the distinction between logical and non-logical words is immanent,would seem to be“for each such choice,logical truthsunder the choiceare true purely by virtue of the meanings of thechosenlogical words”.Formulated in this way,LD is not absurd,and(3)of PLAr1 does not seem to be the right thing to say.

    Given the new formulation,we think that the advocate of LD can reject the abovementioned implication of(3)by at least two ways,one of which is quite straightforward,while the other is more roundabout.The straightforward way is to count all those sentences as“true purely by virtue of languagesimpliciter”that come out logically true undersomechoice of logical words.8Quine([12],p.96)actually hinted this way of rejecting(3)of PLAr1,but he then quickly changed the topic and moved to another argument against LD.After all,LD is nothing but the claim that logical truths are analytical truths;so,as long as logical truths are true purely by virtue of the meanings ofsomewords in them,it really does not matter whether these words appear on this or that list of“l(fā)ogical words”.The roundabout way is to try to define in a transcendent way a category of wordsCthat willincludeevery“ordinary”logical word.9It may or may not contain other words,but this is irrelevant to the current issue.Note that,even if Quine is right about the immanency of the logical/non-logical distinction,it is still not excluded that some broader category C that includes ordinary logical words as a part can be defined in a transcendent way.One obvious candidate for such a category is just the category“words”.If the advocate of LD succeeds in doing this,s/he can then claim that logical truths are true purely by virtue of the meanings ofsomewords inC,hence true purely by virtue of the language;10This category C may or may not have the further use of defining the category of logical words,but this further use is irrelevant to the current issue.and this claim would also make PLAr1 totally irrelevant to the sustainability of LD.Can the advocate of LD find such a categoryC?We think s/he can.What we have in mind is what Quine used to call“words that occursessentiallyin a sentence”.In order to explain it,let us follow Quine’s idea(1936,p.80)a bit.Let us say that an expression E occurs vacuously in a sentenceSiff its replacement by any and every other grammatically admissible expression leaves the truth-value of the sentence unchanged.Sentences after such a replacement are called the“vacuous variants”ofS.Let us also say that an expression E occurs essentially in a sentenceSiff it occurs in all the vacuous variants ofS.So far we have been following Quine,but now let us take a step further and say that an expression E is essentialsimpliciteriff it occurs in all vacuous variants ofsome sentence S.The category“words that are essentialsimpliciter”must include all ordinary logical words as a part,for each of the latter occurs essentially in at least one sentence.11But it seems to us that the category will not include words like“John”and“it”.There may or may not be other words that are essentialsimpliciter,but this is not of our concerned.It is arguably that this definition of“words that are essentialsimpliciter”is a transcendent one.If the advocate of LD claims that logical truths are true purely by virtue of the meanings ofsomewords that is essentialsimpliciter,this claim would make PLAr1 and its premises totally irrelevant to the sustainability of LD.We thus see that both(3)of PLAr1 and PLAr1 itself do not bite.

    But Quine had another argument against LD in PL,though it seems to aim only at the metaphysical version of LD rather than the common presupposition of both versions of LD.Quine wrote(p.96):

    …How,given certain circumstances and a certain true sentence,might we hope to show that the sentence was true by virtue of those circumstances? If we could show that the sentence was logically implied by sentences describing those circumstances,could more be asked? But any sentence logically implies the logical truths.Trivially,then,the logical truths are true by virtue of any circumstances you care to name—language,the world,anything.

    We may call the argument contained in this paragraph“PLAr2”and reformulate it more explicitly as follows:

    (1)A sentenceSis true by virtue of a circumstanceC12It does not matter whether we use the singular noun“circumstance”or the plural noun“circumstances”here,for our argument below will go through for either version.If one insists to use the plural,however,s/he can replace(1)of this argument by(1′):(1′)A sentence S is true by virtue of circumstances C1,C2,...,Cn iff〈DC1〉∧〈DC2〉∧...∧〈DCn〉logically implies S.Given that we have plural quantifiers at our disposal,we can still argue for the same conclusion for(1′)as we do for(1).iff the description〈DC〉ofClogically implies S.13In what follows,we use“DC”to stand for the sentence that describes C and“〈DC〉”to refer to the name of the sentence that describes C.

    (2)The description of whatever circumstance implies every logical truth.

    (3)Therefore,by(1)and(2),a logical truth is true by virtue of every circumstance,linguistic or not,and hence LD is false.

    Again,we think that PLAr2 has a valid form but one of its premise,i.e.,(1),is objectionable.Note that(2)in PLAr2 is entailed by the trivial truth that every sentence whatsoever logically implies every logical truth,and hence should not be doubted.Notice also that,by“circumstances”,Quine must mean something like facts,partly for the reason that,otherwise,(1)of PLAr2 will be obviously false simply because of the fact that every truth is logically implied by the description of,but is not true by virtue of,a contradictory circumstance,but mainly for the reason that a circumstance is supposed to be something like a truth-maker,i.e.,something that is responsible for the truth of a true sentence.We shall name this plausible assumption“factuality of circumstances”that circumstances are fact-like entities.We shall also assume,which seems to us to be equally plausible,that every true sentence describes some circumstance and we shall name this further assumption“comprehension principle(CP)”.Once we make these two plausible assumptions explicit,however,it becomes apparent that(1)of PLAr2 is objectionable for at least two related reasons.

    First of all,(1)of PLAr2 logically implies the following principle(P1):

    (P1)IfSis true by virtue of a circumstanceCwhose description is〈DC〉,thenSis also true by virtue of any circumstanceC*whose description〈DC*〉logically implies〈DC〉.14Here is the proof of the obvious claim that (1)of PLAr2 logically implies (P1).Suppose that S is true by virtue of a circumstance C whose description is〈DC〉.Suppose further that the description〈DC*〉of C* logically implies〈DC〉.By the transitivity of logical implication,the description〈DC*〉of C* logically implies S.Then,by(1)of PLAr2,S is true by virtue of C*.

    (P1)in turn implies,to give just a few examples,that“Quine is a philosopher”is true by virtue of the circumstance whose description is“China is in Asia and(if China is in Asia then Quine is a philosopher)”and that“Quine is Quine”is true by virtue of the circumstance whose description is“China is in Asia”.To us,these results are so counter-intuitive that they jointly constitute a good reason to reject(1)or PLAr2,but we are also very sure that Quine would not be moved by these consequences.So we will not put too much emphasis on this objection.

    Our second objection to (1)in PLAr2 comes from a slingshot-style argument which endeavors to show thatany truthwhatsoever will be true by virtue of“any circumstances you care to name”if(1)of PLAr2 is true.Here is how the argument goes.LetSbe an arbitrary truth that is implied by the description〈DC〉of a certain circumstanceC,so thatSis true by virtue ofCaccording to (1)of PLAr2.Now,letC*be another arbitrarily chosen circumstance and〈DC*〉be its description.The following“proof”shows thatSis also true by virtue ofC*:

    In the above proof,“TDD”refers to any reasonable theory of definite descriptions such as Russell’s theory of definite descriptions,and the premise 3 is justified by the factuality assumption that circumstances are fact-like entities.(P1)and(CP)are principles mentioned in the previous paragraph,while(P2)is the following“principle of extensionality”:

    (P2)If“t1”and“t2”refer to the same thing,then“φ(t1)”and“φ(t2)”describe the same circumstances.

    As one can easily check,each step of the above“proof”is either justified or valid.This then is the“proof”endeavoring to show that any truth whatsoever is true by virtue of any circumstance you care to name if(1)of PLAr1 is true!

    Frankly,what this“proof”really shows is that any truth whatsoever is true by virtue of any circumstance if both (1)of PLAr2 and (P2)are true.15(P1)can be ignored,for it is just a logical consequence of(1)of PLAr2.Because of the intuitive plausibility of(CP)and Factuality assumption,we also suggest that we ignore the possibility that one of them is the culprit of the proof.And we take this“proof”to be a proof byreductio ad absurdum.So at least one of these two assumptions must be wrong,but which one is to be blamed? To give up(1)of PLAr2 is to give up the whole argument PLAr2,while to abandon the principle of extensionality is to take circumstances as“intensional entities”.Yet one of the reasons why Quine wanted to deny the existence of intensional entities is that,were they allowed,it would be possible to define the notion of synonym and therefore the notion of analytic truth.16For example,if propositions,which are intensional entities of a sort,were allowed,we could say that two words are synonymous iff one can be substituted for the other without altering the proposition being expressed.Analytic truths can then be defined in the Fregean way:they turn into logical truths when synonyms are replaced with synonyms.We think that,were circumstances qua intensional entities admitted,a similar definition will work by way of circumstances.So to reject(P2)is to risk resuming the analytic/synthetic distinction.Neither choice seems acceptable to Quine.This proof therefore presents a dilemma to Quine,and we see no way that Quine can escape this dilemma.Especially,Quine cannot respond to it by saying that,according to his verification holism,every sentence is indeed“made true”by every circumstance,for this reply would simply beg the question about the ground of logical truths.

    We are inclined to think that the above argument constitutes areductionof Quine’s account of“true by virtue of”in(1)of PLAr2.But what is wrong with that account?Indeed,Quine asked the question:“If we could show that the sentence was logically implied by sentences describing those circumstances,could more be asked?”We think,however,that the advocate of LD could ask more,and the following remark indicates what that more is.The advocate of LD can first distinguish within circumstances“l(fā)ogical”ones from“non-logical”ones.Intuitively,logical circumstances are those that are described by logical truths or involve meaning stipulations or meaning conventions about logical words only,while non-logical circumstances are those that are described by non-logical truths and usually involve at least something beyond meaning stipulations.S/he can then point out two parallel truths about truths in general:(a)every truth is true at least partly by virtue of the language;and (b)every truth is logically implied by the description of some circumstance.Noticing the parallel between(a)and(b),s/he can then identify them as one and the same truth and propose:to say of a true sentenceSthat it islogicallyimplied by the description of some circumstanceC,no matter what kind of circumstanceCbelongs to,is just to say that it is true at least partly by virtue of the language.It is obvious that every true sentence is,by this definition,true at least partly by virtue of the language.However,if it turns out thatallcircumstances whose descriptions logically imply a sentencesSare of the non-logical kind,Swill also be said to be true partly by virtue of the world.Otherwise,(i.e.,if at least one circumstance whose description logically impliesSis of the logical kind)Swill be said to be truepurelyby virtue of language.In short,according to the advocate of LD,the right-hand part of(1)of PLAr2 is more adequate as definiens for“Sis true at least partly by virtue of the language”than as that for“Sis true by virtue of the circumstanceC”.To define“Sis true by virtue of the circumstanceC,”the advocate of LD can and should ask more than what Quine had offered!17More precisely,the advocate of LD will give the following definitions.A sentence S is true at least partly by virtue of the language iff there is a circumstance C whose description 〈DC〉 logically implies S.A sentence is true only partly by virtue of the language iff(i)it is true at least partly by virtue of the language,and (ii)every sentence that both describes some circumstance and logically implyes S describes some non-logical circumstance.A sentence is true purely by virtue of the language iff(i)it is true at least partly by virtue of the language,and (ii)it is not true only partly by virtue of the language.Given the plausible assumption that a logical truth S describes a circumstance C iff C is a logical circumstance,s/he can go on to show that all and only logical truths are true purely by virtue of the language.If s/he further wants to define the relation“S is true by virtue of C”,s/he can say that a sentence S is true by virtue of a circumstance C iff(i)the description〈DC〉of C logically implies S,and(ii)either〈DC〉describes some logical circumstance or every sentence that both describes some circumstance and logically implies S describes some non-logical circumstance.With the same assumption that a logical truth S describes a circumstance C iff C is a logical circumstance,s/he can show by this last definition both(a)that non-logical truths are true only by virtue of non-logical circumstances and(b)that logical truths are true only by virtue of logical circumstances.

    We can imagine how Quine would respond to our remarks in the previous paragraph:“The distinction you make between logical and non-logical circumstances not only begs the question of the analytic/synthetic distinction but also is empty in the sense that it is indistinguishable from the non-objectionable distinction between the broadest traits of reality and local traits of reality.So,in the end,you have not shown me that there are sentences that are truepurelyby virtue of language.”But our remarks do not beg the question of the analytic/synthetic distinction,for the logical/non-logical distinction between circumstances is not the same as the analytic/synthetic distinction,nor does the former implies the latter.The logical/non-logical distinction between circumstances appeals to the notion of logical words and/or the notion of logical truths that are both legitimate even to Quine.So Quine is not in a position to complain on this distinction at all.As to Quine’s complaint that our distinction is empty,we will deal with it in next section.

    2 Quine’s Arguments against LD in His Early Writings

    Quine gave several criticisms and arguments against LD in his early writings.Some of these comments and arguments are directed toward the epistemic version of LD,while others toward the metaphysical one.The most often discussed argument of Quine against the epistemic version of LD is the vicious regress or the infinite regress argument according to which logical truths cannot be justified by meaningconventions18By“conventions”,Quine ([9],pp.117-118)meant legislative convention rather than discursive convention.The former make“deliberate choices and[set]them forth unaccompanied by any attempt at justification other than in terms of elegance and convenience.These adoptions,called postulates,and their logical consequences(via elementary logic),are true until further notice.”The latter“is mere selection,from a pre-existing body of truths,of certain ones for us as a basis from which to derive others,initially known or unknown.”To give us examples of legislative convention,Quine went on to say(p.120)that postulates of deviant logics are legislative postulates.As examples of discursive convention,readers can think of axioms of,say,Peano’s arithmetic system.,since

    …the logical truths,being infinite in number,must be given by general conventions rather than singly;and logic is needed then in the metatheory,in order to apply the general conventions to individual cases.([9],p.115)19A relevant but not so obviously the same argument as the vicious regress argument by Quine is the argument that,once we try to formulate those general conventions,we inevitably use the very same logical constants that we try to define implicitly by these conventions.Thus,general conventions circumscribing the meaning of logical constants presuppose meaningfulness of those logical constants that are supposed to be meaningless before we give the conventions.Even though it is not so clear that this argument is the same one as the vicious regress argument,this“self-presupposition problem”is avoided in the same way in Boghossian’s proposal.

    We will,however,put this vicious regress argument completely aside in what follows,not because we think that it is unanswerable,but because,on the contrary,we think that its power has been greatly diminished to the minimum by the responses of several philosophers,especially that given by Boghossian ([2]).Boghossian’s response to Quine’s vicious regress argument can be summarized as follows.Logical words(such as“and”and“not”)mean what they mean by virtue of figuring in certain inferential rules involving them (such as the rule of“and”-introduction and the rule of“not”-introduction).The mere“grasp”of these inferential rules suffices for us to be justified in holding true infinitely many logical truths by simply deducing them from these inferential rules alone.The vicious regress problem is avoided because our“grasp”of these inferential rules does not reside in our explicitly writing these rules down in propositional forms but in our beingdisposedto conform to them in our employment of these logical words.So it is not true that,when deducing a logical truth,we need logic again to apply the general conventions to individual cases,says Boghossian.Here,we totally agree with Boghossian and think that the vicious regress problem is no more a threat to the advocate of LD.

    What we want to focus on in the rest of this section is another criticism on LD given by Quine in several places,namely the criticism that LD is empty.However,there are,we think,at least three different senses of the criticism“LD is empty”when Quine said it.The first sense is that LD,when interpreted in a certain way,is true of almost every truth.As Quine said:“If in describing logic…as true by convention what is meant is that the primitivescanbe conventionally circumscribed in such a fashion as to generate all and only the accepted truths of logic…,the characterization is empty;… the same might be said of any other body of doctrine as well.”([10],p.102)20Quine([9],p.121)re-asserted the same point in this way:“What seemed to smack of convention…was‘deliberate choice,set forth unaccompanied by any attempt at justification other than in terms of elegance and convenience’;and to what theoretical hypothesis of natural science might not this same character be attributed?”The second sense is that LD amounts to the non-objectionable but empty claim that logical truths are obvious truths.As Quine said:“… if we try to warp the linguistic doctrine of logical truth around into something like an experimental thesis,21Namely,the thesis that deductively irresoluble disagreement as to a logical truth is evidence of deviation in usage(or meanings)of words.([12],p.112)…[it]seems to imply nothing that is not already by the fact the elementary logic is obvious or can be resolved into obvious steps.”([9],p.112)Indeed,Quine even claimed“… logic is obvious;potentially obvious.Logical truths are tied to translation in no deeper sense … than other obvious truths,e.g.,utterances of ‘It is raining’ in the rain.”([12],pp.96-97)The third sense Quine attached to the term“empty”when he said that LD was empty is that saying that a logical truth,such as“(x)(x=x)”,is true purely by virtue of the meanings of logical words occurring in it is indistinguishable from saying that it is true by virtue of an obvious trait of everything.([9],p.113)We will comment on each of these three senses of“empty”in turn in what follows.

    If LD is interpreted,Quine said,as the doctrine that the meanings of logical wordscanbe circumscribed through conventional assignment of truth to various axioms(or axiom schemata)and rules in such a way as to generatealland only logical truths,then this“axiomatizational style”of characterization can also be carried beyond logic into mathematics and all empirical sciences.However,if one notices the italic word“all”used here,it is clear that primitives in mathematics cannot be22Due to Godel’s incompleteness theorem.,and it is dubious that primitives in other sciences can be,characterized in the same way that logical words of first-order language are characterized.However,people who are sympathetic with Quine might reply that we should drop the word“all”used here anyway for it excludes too much from the realm of logic23Higher-order logic,for example..We tend to agree with this reply,but then think that Hellman’s reply to Quine*24Quine* is a fictional character in[4].is quite right here even if we drop the word“all”used here.According to Hellman([4],p.190),even though Carnap preferred to use the method of axiomatization to stipulate meanings for logical words inLogical Syntax,this nonetheless must not obscure the fact that the central thesis of LD is simply that logical truths are true solely in virtue of the meanings of the logical words.The meanings of these logical words can be given by any of a given number of ways,e.g.,by truth-tables as in the case of truth-functional connectives,or by direct specification of extensions as in the case of identity,or even by inferential rules as envisioned by Boghossian.Once this is made clear,we think there is no more justification of Quine’s complaint that the same methods of giving meanings to logical words can be applied to any other body of the total science.

    What then of the second sense of“empty”? No doubt,logical truths are obvious or,at least,can be reached by obvious steps.But is a logical truth tied to translation in no deeper sense than the obvious truth“it is raining”uttered in the rain? Perhaps so,but this is not the crucial issue here.What is crucial is that we need an account of why logic is obvious.As Hellman([4],p.192)said:“[W]e need an account of why logic is obvious.The sort of account we can give of why‘It is raining’is obvious does not work for logic.Here is a major explanatory role for the linguistic doctrine,essentially its traditional role in logical epistemology.”Hellman did not go on to explain why the sort of account we can give of the obviousness of“it is raining”does not work for logical truths,but we think what he had in mind must be something like the following.When someone utters the obvious truth“it is raining”in the rain,it is obvious whatin the worldmakes that sentence true,namely,the rain.However,if someone utters the equally obvious truth“if it is sunny then it is sunny”also in the rain,it isnotobvious whatin the worldmakes that sentence true.In fact,it seems obvious thatnothing in the worldcould be plausibly said to make the latter sentence true.After all,not only can“if it is sunny then it is sunny”be uttered truly when it is raining,it can also be uttered truly when it is foggy,when it is stormy,when it is at night,when the sun explodes and disappears,or even when there had never been a sun at all in the whole world.So it seems totally inadequate to say that it is made true by any trait of anything in the world at all.Where,then,does the obviousness of its truth come from? LD explains its obviousness in terms of the meanings of the logical word“if…then…”contained in that sentence,and this seems to be an intuitively plausible way to explain the phenomenon.In short,suppose we warp LD around into an experimental thesis,even if doing so will make LD seem to imply nothing that is not already implied by the fact that the elementary logic is obvious or can be resolved into obvious steps,the obviousness of logical truths still needs an explanation that is different from the one given to other obvious non-logical truths.An intuitively suitable explanation is just that logical truths are obvious because of the meanings of the logical words contained in them.

    However,this soon leads us to the third sense that LD is empty.What is the difference,asked Quine,between claiming that“(x)(x=x)”depends for its truth on traits of language and claiming that it depends for its truth on an obvious trait,viz.,self-identity,of its subject matter,viz.,everything? And he replied:“[t]he tendency of our present reflections is that there is no difference.”([9],p.113)We must confess that we don’t have the tendency that Quine had.On the contrary,we have a tendency to say that there are quite a few differences between them.We can see at least four differences.First,if one utters the logical truth“if it is raining then it is raining”,Quine will have to say that there is no difference between claiming that it depends for its truth on traits of language and claiming that it depends for its truth on an obvious trait of its subject matter.But what is the subject matter of this sentence? What does“it”refers to here? It is not so clear what the answer is.25“It is raining”is an example of what Strawson called a“feature-placing statement.”Strawson said that feature-placing statements introduce universals“even if they do not by themselves supply an adequate basis for particular-introduction on the required scale.”But,if“it is raining”does not have a subject matter,so is the sentence“if it is raining so it is raining”.For Strawson on feature-placing statements,readers are referred to[15],p.202.So there seems to be a difference between these two ways of claiming things:it is clear what the former claim is about whereas it is not so clear for the latter.Second,if one utters“if Sherlock Holmes exists then Sherlock Holmes exists”,Quine will,again,have to say that there is no difference between claiming that it depends for its truth on traits of language and claiming that it depends for its truth on an obvious trait of its subject matter.But what is the subject matter of this sentence? What does“Sherlock Holmes”refers to here?Nothing! Again,there seems to be a difference between these two ways of claiming things:the former claim is clearly about existents objects,viz.,logical words,while the latter appears not to be about anything at all.Third,claiming that a logical truth depends for its truth on an obvious trait of its subject matter will,while claiming that it depends for its truth on traits of language will not,very likely provoke a doubt in non-philosophers whether therereallyis such a trait asself-identity,orbeing red or not being red,or evenif being red then being blue or not being blue,in its subject matter.Hellman used to call these traits“stipulated universal traits”probably because he,like us,also saw the artificiality of these so-called“universal traits”.Here again,we seem to have a difference between these two ways of claiming things:the former claim is ontologically innocent in a way that the latter is not.Fourth,as Carnap([3],p.920)pointed out,both ways of claiming things are empirically testable,but the responses that will confirm one of them will be quite different from the responses that will confirm the other.The man who believes that“(x)(x=x)”depends for its truth on an obvious trait of everything will,while the man who believes that it depends for its truth on traits of language will not,prepare to retract his judgment in the hypothetical situation of witnessing a counterexample.So here we seem to have a fourth difference between these two ways of claiming things:they have different empirical confirmation conditions.

    So far,we have checked 4 different arguments against LD given by Quine.After carefully inspecting each one of them,we find that none of them is compelling.There may be other arguments of Quine aiming at LD that we have overlooked,and there may be other ways of arguing against LD that Quine had not considered.We should not,therefore,conclude that LD is true.Instead,we conclude that Quine’s arguments against LD are at best inconclusive and that LD,and hence the analytic/synthetic distinction,is still a defensible doctrine.

    91在线观看av| 欧美日韩中文字幕国产精品一区二区三区| 欧洲精品卡2卡3卡4卡5卡区| 99热这里只有是精品50| 国产午夜精品久久久久久一区二区三区 | 日韩欧美精品v在线| 亚洲av电影不卡..在线观看| 久久久久久大精品| 看黄色毛片网站| 中国美女看黄片| 国产精品av视频在线免费观看| 国产伦一二天堂av在线观看| 国产真实乱freesex| 亚洲av成人av| 夜夜看夜夜爽夜夜摸| 久久久久久久久久久丰满 | 最新中文字幕久久久久| 老熟妇乱子伦视频在线观看| 日本欧美国产在线视频| 国产视频一区二区在线看| 亚洲无线观看免费| 可以在线观看的亚洲视频| 神马国产精品三级电影在线观看| 99精品在免费线老司机午夜| aaaaa片日本免费| 我的女老师完整版在线观看| 亚洲天堂国产精品一区在线| 床上黄色一级片| 午夜福利在线观看免费完整高清在 | 色噜噜av男人的天堂激情| 日韩一区二区视频免费看| 日韩亚洲欧美综合| 波多野结衣高清作品| 亚洲精品日韩av片在线观看| 老女人水多毛片| 亚洲综合色惰| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区 | 日韩欧美在线乱码| 精品久久久久久成人av| 久久6这里有精品| 日本欧美国产在线视频| 国产老妇女一区| 久久国内精品自在自线图片| 91久久精品电影网| 国内精品久久久久精免费| 免费观看的影片在线观看| 国产精品一区二区三区四区久久| 成人国产综合亚洲| 乱系列少妇在线播放| 12—13女人毛片做爰片一| 日本三级黄在线观看| 国产伦人伦偷精品视频| 男女啪啪激烈高潮av片| 国产aⅴ精品一区二区三区波| 观看美女的网站| 国产精品亚洲一级av第二区| 尤物成人国产欧美一区二区三区| 亚洲黑人精品在线| 最新中文字幕久久久久| 看十八女毛片水多多多| 成人亚洲精品av一区二区| 日韩av在线大香蕉| 国产三级在线视频| 伦理电影大哥的女人| 最近最新中文字幕大全电影3| 日本爱情动作片www.在线观看 | 国产精品日韩av在线免费观看| 国产免费男女视频| 免费观看精品视频网站| 亚洲精品乱码久久久v下载方式| 国产精品嫩草影院av在线观看 | 中文字幕高清在线视频| 女的被弄到高潮叫床怎么办 | 51国产日韩欧美| 国产高清有码在线观看视频| 久久精品国产自在天天线| 伊人久久精品亚洲午夜| 亚洲人与动物交配视频| 亚洲国产欧美人成| 搡女人真爽免费视频火全软件 | 搡老岳熟女国产| 免费看光身美女| 久久草成人影院| 一区二区三区四区激情视频 | 黄色配什么色好看| 国产精品伦人一区二区| 欧美黑人巨大hd| 久久精品国产清高在天天线| 欧美三级亚洲精品| 精品久久久久久成人av| 五月玫瑰六月丁香| 此物有八面人人有两片| 伦精品一区二区三区| 欧美高清性xxxxhd video| 亚洲精品久久国产高清桃花| 美女黄网站色视频| 老熟妇仑乱视频hdxx| 观看免费一级毛片| 免费看av在线观看网站| a级毛片a级免费在线| 国产一区二区在线av高清观看| 偷拍熟女少妇极品色| 伊人久久精品亚洲午夜| 黄色欧美视频在线观看| 极品教师在线视频| 久久精品久久久久久噜噜老黄 | 国产精品女同一区二区软件 | av视频在线观看入口| 在线免费观看的www视频| 我的老师免费观看完整版| 国产色婷婷99| 麻豆国产av国片精品| 亚洲精品国产成人久久av| 婷婷精品国产亚洲av在线| 久久久久免费精品人妻一区二区| 51国产日韩欧美| 草草在线视频免费看| 国产精品福利在线免费观看| 欧美又色又爽又黄视频| 五月伊人婷婷丁香| 真人做人爱边吃奶动态| 热99re8久久精品国产| 国产高清有码在线观看视频| 噜噜噜噜噜久久久久久91| 男人舔女人下体高潮全视频| 精品不卡国产一区二区三区| 天堂av国产一区二区熟女人妻| 亚洲国产精品久久男人天堂| 给我免费播放毛片高清在线观看| 色综合站精品国产| 婷婷色综合大香蕉| ponron亚洲| 婷婷亚洲欧美| 亚洲欧美精品综合久久99| 亚洲七黄色美女视频| 美女黄网站色视频| 久久人人精品亚洲av| 亚洲成人免费电影在线观看| 国产在线男女| 亚洲国产精品久久男人天堂| 精品无人区乱码1区二区| 国产麻豆成人av免费视频| 99在线视频只有这里精品首页| 久久久久九九精品影院| 一区二区三区免费毛片| 国模一区二区三区四区视频| 精品久久久久久久末码| 91久久精品国产一区二区成人| 最近中文字幕高清免费大全6 | 国产大屁股一区二区在线视频| 少妇的逼好多水| 免费高清视频大片| 十八禁网站免费在线| 欧美+亚洲+日韩+国产| 成人高潮视频无遮挡免费网站| 淫妇啪啪啪对白视频| 久久久国产成人精品二区| 午夜精品久久久久久毛片777| 人妻少妇偷人精品九色| 日韩高清综合在线| 亚洲精品影视一区二区三区av| 99在线人妻在线中文字幕| 美女免费视频网站| 国产免费一级a男人的天堂| 动漫黄色视频在线观看| 欧美日韩综合久久久久久 | 91久久精品国产一区二区三区| 搡老岳熟女国产| 少妇被粗大猛烈的视频| 亚洲av中文av极速乱 | 亚洲专区国产一区二区| 中文字幕av在线有码专区| 亚洲第一电影网av| 精品久久久久久久久亚洲 | 欧美最新免费一区二区三区| 91精品国产九色| 欧美激情在线99| or卡值多少钱| 国产精品,欧美在线| 精品久久久久久,| 欧美日韩国产亚洲二区| 亚洲在线自拍视频| 午夜福利成人在线免费观看| 一级黄片播放器| 国产淫片久久久久久久久| 中国美女看黄片| 欧美性猛交╳xxx乱大交人| 日本精品一区二区三区蜜桃| 成人国产麻豆网| 天天一区二区日本电影三级| 午夜视频国产福利| 亚洲在线观看片| 极品教师在线视频| 成年人黄色毛片网站| 天美传媒精品一区二区| av在线天堂中文字幕| а√天堂www在线а√下载| 91午夜精品亚洲一区二区三区 | 国产一区二区在线av高清观看| 99热网站在线观看| 悠悠久久av| 三级国产精品欧美在线观看| 亚洲成人免费电影在线观看| 91狼人影院| 99久国产av精品| 国产日本99.免费观看| 国产精品嫩草影院av在线观看 | 亚洲国产欧洲综合997久久,| 美女大奶头视频| 12—13女人毛片做爰片一| 亚洲色图av天堂| 久久久久久久久久成人| 日韩在线高清观看一区二区三区 | 免费观看的影片在线观看| 亚洲av一区综合| 欧美日韩精品成人综合77777| 国产精品亚洲美女久久久| 亚洲精品456在线播放app | 国产69精品久久久久777片| 真人一进一出gif抽搐免费| 亚洲aⅴ乱码一区二区在线播放| 国产黄色小视频在线观看| 亚洲熟妇中文字幕五十中出| 午夜a级毛片| 热99在线观看视频| av国产免费在线观看| 亚洲 国产 在线| 久久久久国产精品人妻aⅴ院| 在线观看舔阴道视频| 欧美日韩瑟瑟在线播放| 亚洲va日本ⅴa欧美va伊人久久| 中文字幕人妻熟人妻熟丝袜美| 久9热在线精品视频| 春色校园在线视频观看| 97热精品久久久久久| 国产精品爽爽va在线观看网站| 婷婷精品国产亚洲av在线| 久久精品人妻少妇| 亚洲成人久久性| 亚洲在线自拍视频| 日本在线视频免费播放| 啦啦啦韩国在线观看视频| 久久久久免费精品人妻一区二区| 国产黄片美女视频| 精品一区二区三区人妻视频| 日日啪夜夜撸| 最新中文字幕久久久久| 黄片wwwwww| 国产私拍福利视频在线观看| 深夜精品福利| 久久久成人免费电影| 久久久久久久久久黄片| 九色成人免费人妻av| 久久久精品欧美日韩精品| 亚洲aⅴ乱码一区二区在线播放| 俺也久久电影网| 别揉我奶头~嗯~啊~动态视频| 美女高潮的动态| 直男gayav资源| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜添小说| 内射极品少妇av片p| 国产黄片美女视频| 精品久久久久久久久久久久久| 国产色爽女视频免费观看| 可以在线观看毛片的网站| 久久精品国产亚洲av涩爱 | 亚洲最大成人av| 一边摸一边抽搐一进一小说| 人妻久久中文字幕网| av专区在线播放| 亚洲第一区二区三区不卡| 久久久久久久久大av| 亚洲内射少妇av| 99国产精品一区二区蜜桃av| 最近在线观看免费完整版| 国产日本99.免费观看| 免费一级毛片在线播放高清视频| 九九在线视频观看精品| 亚洲专区中文字幕在线| 亚洲欧美日韩无卡精品| 亚洲自拍偷在线| 亚洲熟妇中文字幕五十中出| 久久九九热精品免费| 亚洲久久久久久中文字幕| 日韩在线高清观看一区二区三区 | 在线观看一区二区三区| 欧美日韩中文字幕国产精品一区二区三区| 亚洲av一区综合| 色精品久久人妻99蜜桃| 国产亚洲欧美98| 国产欧美日韩精品一区二区| 日本成人三级电影网站| 一级a爱片免费观看的视频| 琪琪午夜伦伦电影理论片6080| 99久久无色码亚洲精品果冻| 欧美丝袜亚洲另类 | 免费看a级黄色片| 女生性感内裤真人,穿戴方法视频| 中亚洲国语对白在线视频| 简卡轻食公司| 成年女人毛片免费观看观看9| 国产在线精品亚洲第一网站| 日韩在线高清观看一区二区三区 | 999久久久精品免费观看国产| 精品人妻视频免费看| 久久久久久久久久黄片| 午夜亚洲福利在线播放| 免费观看的影片在线观看| 国产单亲对白刺激| 亚洲人成网站高清观看| 变态另类成人亚洲欧美熟女| 中文字幕av成人在线电影| 一进一出好大好爽视频| 露出奶头的视频| 久久久国产成人免费| 午夜久久久久精精品| 成人永久免费在线观看视频| 亚洲国产高清在线一区二区三| 精品人妻1区二区| www.色视频.com| 搡老妇女老女人老熟妇| 久久久国产成人免费| 老女人水多毛片| 黄色一级大片看看| 久久国产乱子免费精品| 天堂动漫精品| 日韩欧美免费精品| 成人无遮挡网站| 久久久久性生活片| 午夜久久久久精精品| 不卡视频在线观看欧美| 99热只有精品国产| 亚洲精品国产成人久久av| 精品人妻熟女av久视频| 精品久久久久久久久久免费视频| 国产精品98久久久久久宅男小说| 午夜福利欧美成人| 欧美性猛交黑人性爽| a在线观看视频网站| 国产单亲对白刺激| 大又大粗又爽又黄少妇毛片口| 欧美最新免费一区二区三区| 久久精品国产亚洲av香蕉五月| 免费人成视频x8x8入口观看| 成人鲁丝片一二三区免费| 亚洲欧美日韩高清在线视频| 白带黄色成豆腐渣| 久久精品国产自在天天线| 搡老妇女老女人老熟妇| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区 | 色视频www国产| 国产欧美日韩精品一区二区| 亚洲成人久久性| 国产精品一区二区免费欧美| 国产aⅴ精品一区二区三区波| 免费看光身美女| 无遮挡黄片免费观看| 亚洲狠狠婷婷综合久久图片| 国内精品久久久久久久电影| 麻豆一二三区av精品| 欧美+亚洲+日韩+国产| 变态另类丝袜制服| 国内精品宾馆在线| 观看免费一级毛片| 亚洲中文字幕日韩| 五月玫瑰六月丁香| 日韩欧美精品免费久久| 午夜福利成人在线免费观看| 在线播放无遮挡| 中文字幕av成人在线电影| 99久久中文字幕三级久久日本| 91在线精品国自产拍蜜月| 三级毛片av免费| 十八禁国产超污无遮挡网站| 亚洲va日本ⅴa欧美va伊人久久| 欧美一区二区精品小视频在线| 日日撸夜夜添| 免费人成视频x8x8入口观看| 亚洲精品456在线播放app | 欧美bdsm另类| 欧美性感艳星| 无人区码免费观看不卡| av专区在线播放| 日韩欧美 国产精品| 十八禁网站免费在线| 国产亚洲av嫩草精品影院| 日韩欧美在线二视频| 少妇熟女aⅴ在线视频| 午夜影院日韩av| 18禁在线播放成人免费| xxxwww97欧美| 人人妻人人看人人澡| 神马国产精品三级电影在线观看| 国产一区二区在线av高清观看| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区 | 一本精品99久久精品77| 小说图片视频综合网站| 久久久久久久久久黄片| www.www免费av| 欧美极品一区二区三区四区| 伦精品一区二区三区| 日本与韩国留学比较| 91在线精品国自产拍蜜月| 亚洲久久久久久中文字幕| av天堂中文字幕网| 久久中文看片网| 最近中文字幕高清免费大全6 | 国产久久久一区二区三区| 久久香蕉精品热| 99热只有精品国产| 午夜爱爱视频在线播放| 亚洲无线观看免费| 欧美bdsm另类| 99久久无色码亚洲精品果冻| 联通29元200g的流量卡| 国产精品久久久久久亚洲av鲁大| 美女xxoo啪啪120秒动态图| av女优亚洲男人天堂| 亚洲久久久久久中文字幕| 欧美激情久久久久久爽电影| 搡女人真爽免费视频火全软件 | 国产精品1区2区在线观看.| 88av欧美| 午夜激情欧美在线| 午夜日韩欧美国产| 国产午夜精品久久久久久一区二区三区 | av在线蜜桃| 国产精品一区二区三区四区久久| 真人一进一出gif抽搐免费| 欧美潮喷喷水| 男人舔奶头视频| 美女xxoo啪啪120秒动态图| 国产精品久久久久久久久免| 色综合色国产| 久久这里只有精品中国| 99riav亚洲国产免费| 天堂网av新在线| 亚洲成人久久性| 日韩强制内射视频| 99热这里只有是精品在线观看| 在线观看舔阴道视频| 国产真实伦视频高清在线观看 | 亚洲在线自拍视频| 老熟妇仑乱视频hdxx| 亚洲最大成人av| 一级av片app| 欧美日韩瑟瑟在线播放| 他把我摸到了高潮在线观看| 亚洲最大成人手机在线| 免费一级毛片在线播放高清视频| 亚洲av中文av极速乱 | 内地一区二区视频在线| 久久香蕉精品热| 亚洲熟妇熟女久久| 久久久久性生活片| 少妇熟女aⅴ在线视频| 最新中文字幕久久久久| 亚洲av成人精品一区久久| 国产精品美女特级片免费视频播放器| 国产成人一区二区在线| 日本色播在线视频| 成人无遮挡网站| 亚洲av中文字字幕乱码综合| 国产精品久久久久久亚洲av鲁大| 日日干狠狠操夜夜爽| 欧美一级a爱片免费观看看| 最好的美女福利视频网| 性插视频无遮挡在线免费观看| 精品久久久噜噜| 精品人妻1区二区| 精品久久久久久久末码| 国产av麻豆久久久久久久| 亚洲欧美日韩无卡精品| 俺也久久电影网| 国产精品野战在线观看| 黄片wwwwww| 1024手机看黄色片| 不卡视频在线观看欧美| 88av欧美| 国产精品伦人一区二区| av.在线天堂| 日韩欧美免费精品| 老女人水多毛片| 国产av在哪里看| 最后的刺客免费高清国语| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜添小说| 黄片wwwwww| 麻豆成人午夜福利视频| 国内精品一区二区在线观看| 日韩欧美三级三区| 麻豆av噜噜一区二区三区| 999久久久精品免费观看国产| 一级毛片久久久久久久久女| 一本精品99久久精品77| 麻豆久久精品国产亚洲av| 制服丝袜大香蕉在线| 久久久精品大字幕| 久久人人精品亚洲av| 久久天躁狠狠躁夜夜2o2o| 精品人妻一区二区三区麻豆 | 精品欧美国产一区二区三| a级一级毛片免费在线观看| 婷婷色综合大香蕉| 麻豆国产av国片精品| 又黄又爽又免费观看的视频| 亚洲精品色激情综合| 特大巨黑吊av在线直播| 精品人妻偷拍中文字幕| 日本a在线网址| 国产在线精品亚洲第一网站| 一级a爱片免费观看的视频| 1024手机看黄色片| 婷婷亚洲欧美| 久久久精品欧美日韩精品| 51国产日韩欧美| 欧美区成人在线视频| 91久久精品国产一区二区成人| 18+在线观看网站| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 国产欧美日韩精品一区二区| 精品乱码久久久久久99久播| 亚洲欧美激情综合另类| 99久久久亚洲精品蜜臀av| 俺也久久电影网| .国产精品久久| 超碰av人人做人人爽久久| 亚洲熟女精品中文字幕| 熟女人妻精品中文字幕| 精品国产露脸久久av麻豆| 女人十人毛片免费观看3o分钟| 免费看不卡的av| 国产欧美另类精品又又久久亚洲欧美| 久久久久久人妻| 在线观看一区二区三区| 国产无遮挡羞羞视频在线观看| 边亲边吃奶的免费视频| 毛片女人毛片| 插逼视频在线观看| 97热精品久久久久久| 伊人久久精品亚洲午夜| 亚洲国产精品一区三区| 亚洲av中文字字幕乱码综合| 亚洲怡红院男人天堂| 国产无遮挡羞羞视频在线观看| 最近中文字幕2019免费版| 麻豆国产97在线/欧美| 夜夜骑夜夜射夜夜干| 99re6热这里在线精品视频| 狂野欧美激情性xxxx在线观看| 女的被弄到高潮叫床怎么办| 永久网站在线| 中文字幕精品免费在线观看视频 | 久久国产乱子免费精品| videossex国产| 18+在线观看网站| 视频区图区小说| 亚洲欧美中文字幕日韩二区| 久久久久国产网址| 在线观看国产h片| 国产精品一二三区在线看| 欧美最新免费一区二区三区| 久久人人爽av亚洲精品天堂 | 九草在线视频观看| 九九久久精品国产亚洲av麻豆| 十分钟在线观看高清视频www | 中国美白少妇内射xxxbb| 美女国产视频在线观看| 国产人妻一区二区三区在| 国产毛片在线视频| 2018国产大陆天天弄谢| 亚洲第一av免费看| 亚洲精品日韩av片在线观看| 久久精品久久精品一区二区三区| 80岁老熟妇乱子伦牲交| 欧美日韩视频精品一区| 18禁裸乳无遮挡免费网站照片| 精品亚洲乱码少妇综合久久| 国产黄频视频在线观看| 亚洲va在线va天堂va国产| 亚洲欧美成人精品一区二区| 精品国产乱码久久久久久小说| 日韩成人av中文字幕在线观看| 丝瓜视频免费看黄片| 午夜福利在线观看免费完整高清在| 男男h啪啪无遮挡| 亚洲国产欧美在线一区| 少妇熟女欧美另类| 国产精品久久久久久久电影| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜爱| 精品一区二区三卡| 亚洲av成人精品一二三区| 久久久久久久大尺度免费视频| 天天躁夜夜躁狠狠久久av| 国产精品久久久久久精品电影小说 | 一二三四中文在线观看免费高清| 成人午夜精彩视频在线观看| 亚洲av福利一区| 嘟嘟电影网在线观看| 永久免费av网站大全| 国产老妇伦熟女老妇高清| 亚洲最大成人中文| 九色成人免费人妻av| 日韩电影二区| 一区二区av电影网| 国产精品一区www在线观看| 国产淫语在线视频| 日本av免费视频播放| 久久影院123| 男人狂女人下面高潮的视频| 一级毛片黄色毛片免费观看视频| 美女xxoo啪啪120秒动态图| 亚洲国产精品999| 自拍欧美九色日韩亚洲蝌蚪91 | 国产午夜精品久久久久久一区二区三区| 婷婷色综合www|