• <tr id="yyy80"></tr>
  • <sup id="yyy80"></sup>
  • <tfoot id="yyy80"><noscript id="yyy80"></noscript></tfoot>
  • 99热精品在线国产_美女午夜性视频免费_国产精品国产高清国产av_av欧美777_自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇_亚洲熟女精品中文字幕_www日本黄色视频网_国产精品野战在线观看 ?

    Quine was Never Called Quine

    2019-12-18 06:37:32ChaoanHe
    邏輯學(xué)研究 2019年6期

    Chaoan He

    Abstract.In her recent defense of non-metalinguistic Predicativism,Fara appealed to the distinction of two notions of calling to avoid the Kripkean charge of triviality that metalinguistic Predicativism seems to fall prey to.This article attempts to show that Fara’s master argument is deeply flawed,for it is circumscribed within an unexpected pattern of vicious circularity.In order to avoid the Kripkean charge of triviality,she was led to a certain sort of inconsistency;but to avoid such inconsistency,she would most probably be led back to a version of triviality.

    1 Introduction

    Quine,literally,was never called Quine,though he was certainly called‘Quine’.Anyone vigilant of the use-mention distinction would have insisted on something like that.Fara disagrees.In her recent defense of non-metalinguistic Predicativism ([3,4]),Fara contends that sentences such as(1)and(1′)are both grammatical and mean quite different things.

    (1)Quine was called Quine.

    (1′)Quine was called‘Quine’.

    She argued that there are two senses of calling in play here.In theappellativesense of calling,to call a man Quine is to ascribe to him the property of having‘Quine’as a name;and in theaddressingsense of calling,to call a man‘Quine’is to address him by employing the very word‘Quine’.

    This paper attempts to show that Fara’s master argument,based on the above distinction,for her version of Predicativism is deeply flawed—it is as I’ll argue circumscribed within an unexpected pattern of vicious circularity.In order to avoid the Kripkean charge of triviality,she was led to a certain sort of inconsistency;but to avoid such inconsistency,she would probably be led back to a version of triviality.

    2 Avoiding Triviality

    Predicativism of proper names is the view that names should be construed as predicates,rather than referring expressions.Since a predicate,unlike directly referring expressions,applies to certain objects onlyindirectly,in virtue of the objects’meeting the particular application condition associated with the predicate,if proper names are predicates,they should be associated with certain application conditions as well.

    There has been a bunch of metalinguistic accounts of such conditions at market,which hold that a proper name‘N’is true of a thing just in case the thing is given the name‘N’in an appropriate way([2])or it is the bearer of‘N’([1]).These conditions are metalinguistic in the sense that the name occurring in the right hand side of them ismentionedrather than used.For instance,‘Quine’is true of a man just in case he is given the name‘Quine’in an appropriate way,or he is the bearer of‘Quine’.

    It has long been noted that these proposals are vulnerable to a common trouble,that of running afoul of the Kripkean criterion of non-triviality.([5])As the right hand sides of the conditionsmentionthe name,the applicability of the name‘Quine’turns out to be explicated in terms of the name itself.To say that‘Quine’applies to the bearers of‘Quine’,however,seems just as trivial as merely saying that‘Quine’applies to the things applicable to‘Quine’.

    Having the triviality problem in mind,Fara,in her considered view,recommended what she called thebeing called condition([3,4]):

    (BCC)A name‘N’is true of a thing just in case it is called N.

    The prime virtue of BCC is that it offers up equally intuitive application conditions withoutgoing metalinguistic.Without mentioning the name itself in explicating the applicability of a name,the Kripkean charge of triviality would hopefully not arise for BCC in any obvious way.

    Though favorable in that respect,BCC may be censored on a different ground.Consider an instance of the schema,

    (2)‘Quine’is true of a thing just in case it is called Quine.

    Here the word‘Quine’on the right hand side isused.Now,as Fara concedes([3]),people may find sentences as such ungrammatical or unintelligible.For literally,to say that Quine is called Quine is to say that he is called a certain person,the prestigious philosopher himself,whereas the intended meaning is rather that he has‘Quine’as a name.Everything,therefore,turns on the alleged grammaticality and intelligibility of locutions such as‘xis called Quine’or‘xcalledyQuine’.

    Fara’s central observation is that the phrase ‘being called’ could be complimented by typical predicates ([3,4]).For instance,if Jack said that ‘Quine is dimwitted and ignorant’,then it follows that

    (3)Quine was called stupid.

    Quine was here attributed the property of stupidity,though Jack did not use that word.That is very different from the case when Jack said to Quine ‘stupid,come here’,which makes(4)true.

    (4)Quine was called‘stupid’.

    Quine was here simply addressed by the word‘stupid’,without any implication that Jack really thought that Quine was stupid.Quine,for better or for worse,may not mind in the slightest if someone addresses him by the word‘stupid’,but he certainly would mind a lot if someone attributes to him the property of stupidity.Hence the title of Fara’s paper:‘you can call me‘stupid’,…just don’t call me stupid’([3]).

    As typical predicates could compliment the phrase‘being called’,if proper names are predicates,they could compliment the phrase‘being called’as well.Nothing then would deter ‘Quine’ from beingusedgrammatically and intelligibly in ‘xcalledyQuine’ to ascribeya property,and the property ascribed is something likehaving‘Quine’ as a name.The seemingly striking ungrammaticality or unintelligibility of‘xcalledyQuine’ only stems from the traditional,but prejudiced,view of seeing names as referring devices rather than predicates.

    Fara’s argument,as Savage fairly observed([6]),is one by analogy.She attempts to establish the grammaticality and intelligibility of‘xcalledy z’when‘z’is a proper name from considerations of the grammaticality and intelligibility of ‘xcalledy z’when ‘z’ is a typical predicate.I shall argue in the following that Fara is therein committed to two crucial assumptions,which I shall call CAT and NE respectively.

    First,as togrammaticality,Fara’s analogy could be questioned on the ground that it may rest on some sort of category mistake,something like what we find in an argument by analogy for the grammaticality of‘seven is heavier than five’,from considerations of the grammaticality of‘John is heavier than Jill’and the linguistic fact that‘seven’and‘five’are proper names as‘John’and‘Jill’are.

    Fara’s idea is that,since typical predicates can grammatically compliment the appellative‘being called’,and proper names are predicates as typical predicates are,proper names must be able to grammatically compliment the appellative‘being called’as well.But as Fara herself pointed out,predicates are‘not all syntactically alike’.([4])Count nouns can,but mass nouns cannot,complement‘how many’,though both are nouns.Simply by being nouns is no guarantee that if one kind of nouns occur grammatically in a certain construction then another kind of noun should also occur grammatically in that same construction.

    It is similarly sensible that simply by being predicates is no full guarantee that if typical predicates can grammatically compliment the appellative‘being called’then proper names as predicates should also grammatically compliment the appellative‘being called’.Just as‘how many’is not applicable to all kinds of nouns,‘being called’may not be applicable to all kinds of predicates.And just as we have to distinguish sub-categories among nouns,we may also need to distinguish sub-categories among predicates.

    Thus for her argument by analogy to work,Fara has to endorse the following category assumption:

    (CAT)Proper names and typical predicates belong to the same sub-category of predicates in terms of their applicability relative to the appellative ‘being called’.1This sub-category,of course,may turn out to be identical to the category of predicates itself,if the appellative‘being called’applies to all predicates,of whatever kind,across the board.

    And second,turning tointelligibility,even if its grammaticality is granted,the calling relation in question may fall a victim of equivocation.Fara has been cautious in distinguishing appellative calling from addressing calling.This fine distinction,however,may not be sufficient to guarantee the validity of Fara’s argument by analogy.For even if the calling relation in her argument is uniformly appellative,there may still be room for further equivocation to arise.In the ridicule of claiming that‘Stephen Hawking is faster than Usain Bolt’in the face of the obvious fact that Bolt runs faster than any other man in the world of his heyday,the relation‘xis faster thany’has been subject to equivocation.The obvious fact is that Bolt runs(physically)faster than any other,while the ridicule is rather that Hawking is (mentally)faster than Bolt.The relations expressed by‘xis faster thany’in those two cases,nevertheless,can fairly be said to constitute asui generiskind of some level.For in both,the expression syntactically bonds two individual-names and semantically ascribes the relation of comparative advantage in speed.But that obviously is no guarantee that the two cases should be taken on a par.‘Stephen Hawking is faster than Usain Bolt’is only intelligible when interpreted in a very different way from‘Usain Bolt is faster than Stephen Hawking’.If the two sentences are given similar interpretations,no matter this is done in line with the measure of physical advantage in speed or of mental advantage in speed,we are to end up with an out-and-out contradiction,or unintelligibility.

    For similar reasons,Fara’s appellative calling,though asui generiskind of relation in itself,may also fall prey to equivocation in its varying applications.When it is applied to ordinary predicates,it is intelligible in one way,but when applied to names,it may turn out to be intelligibleonlyin some other way.If that is to be ruled out,for her argument by analogy to work,Fara has to maintain an assumption of non-equivocation:

    (NE)The appellative calling relation is non-equivocal in its applications to proper names and typical predicates.

    These two assumptions of Fara,it is to be shown in the following,are inconsistent with certain vital considerations Fara herself would most probably like to endorse.And to get out of the inconsistency,Fara may find herself back into trouble with the Kripkean Triviality charge she attempts to avoid in the first place.

    3 Inconsistency

    Fara attempts to avoid triviality by endorsing BCC.So now,even if granted that BCC for names is both grammatical and intelligible,is it really non-trivial? Fara offered a concise argument(ARG)for the affirmative answer([3]):

    (a)Names are predicates.

    (b)If names are predicates,then if BCC for names were trivially true,analogous BCC schemata for other predicates would have been trivially true.2An analogous BCC schema for other predicates is roughly this:a predicate‘P’is true of a thing just in case it is called P.

    (c)Analogous BCC schemata for other predicates are not trivially true,for they are not even true.

    (d)Therefore,BCC for names is not trivially true.

    As Fara’s examples illustrate,the premise(c)is indisputable.For to call a thingX,‘X’ being a typical predicate such as a count noun,a mass noun or an adjective,is certainly not sufficient to guarantee that‘X’is really true of the thing.You can call me stupid,but the word ‘stupid’ is not true of me,for I’m not really stupid.Given that(a)is the master thesis of Predicativism and(b),arguably,a corollary of Fara’s assumption CAT,the argument ARG seems to make a strong case for the non-triviality of BCC for names.

    But a closer look at it would leave one with the puzzle how ARG could even be an argument as intended.Given the logic of ARG,we could similarly advance an argument against the very thesis that BCC for names is true.If viable,the argument would not only undermine ARG,but threatens the entire project of Fara’s Predicativism itself.Here is it(ARG*):

    (a*)Names are predicates.

    (b*)If names are predicates,then if BCC for names were true,analogous BCC schemata for other predicates would have been true.

    (c*)Analogous BCC schemata for other predicates are not true.

    (d*)Therefore,BCC for names is not true.

    Here the only way available for Fara to debunk this argument is to reject the premise(b*).But she clearly accepts its counterpart(b).Why the difference? Given the commonality between names and other predicates spelled out in CAT,if the agreement between BCC for names and that for other predicates in terms ofbeing trivially trueis taken for granted in ARG,then why not grant their agreement in terms ofbeing true? So if(b*)is to be squarely ruled out,the commonality between names and other predicates must be verytightwhen it comes to triviality,but it has to belooseenough to permit a vital difference when it comes to truth value.Given the intimate connections between something’sbeing trivially trueand itstruth valueitself,however,it is hard to see how the extent of such looseness could be satisfactorily drawn out without at the same time leaving the cherished tight commonality spelled out in CAT breaking down.

    This line of thought is not meant to prove that Fara’s argument for the nontriviality of BBCper seis invalid,but to make the preliminary observation that the argument’s premises may land her in troubles.And to get out of such troubles may require additional assumptions inconsistent with her initial assumptions CAT and NE,as to be shown soon.And there are a couple of further observations of appellative calling relation when applied to ordinary predicates and to proper names,which would help making the same point.

    First,there is theauthority difference.As Fara pointed out([3]),any one,if she wishes,can call Quine stupid,but not just any one are in a position to call him Quine.Only those entitled can! Appellative calling,when applied to names,requires a certain sort of authority.In relation to this,there is thefact difference.Though someone’s being called stupid does not imply in the least that he is stupid,someone’s being called Quine certainly implies the fact that he is Quine.Still,there is thewording difference.Someone may call Quine stupid without ever using the word‘stupid’—she could achieve this by using the words‘dim-witted and ignorant’,but no one could call the man Quine without at some point,directly or indirectly,using the name itself.If Quine could be so named without using the word itself,as Savage pointed out([6]),then it would be unsettledwhich namehas been given to him and,it is not clear why Quine could not have been so named by using a distinct expression,say‘Quinten’.

    If names and ordinary predicates are predicates alike,why those differences,and the different verdicts between(b)and(b*)? As there are only two elements involved in the phenomena,the appellative calling relation on the one hand,and the expressions complimenting ‘being called’ on the other,there would seem to be only two ways of explaining the differences.In one way,Fara may locate the root of the differences in the expressions complimenting‘being called’.If so,she would probably embrace something like the idea that names and ordinary predicates are of different sub-categories of predicates when applied to the same calling relation,which is utterly inconsistent with her assumption CAT.On inspection,however,this conclusion may seem hasty.Fara may argue that names and ordinary predicates both belong to a sub-category C1in the assumption CAT,whereas they merely do not belong to a different sub-category C2to such an effect that (b*)does not obtain.Indeed,C1is defined in terms ofgrammatical applicabilityto the appellative‘being called’,while C2seems rather to be defined in terms of thetruth valuesof BCC schemata.Hence to say that names and ordinary predicates do not belong to the same sub-category C2,to such an effect that(b*)does not obtain,is not really inconsistent with saying that they both belong to C1.

    This observation,nevertheless,loses sight of one crucial point.For Fara’s ARG to stand,(b)has to obtain,which means that names and ordinary predicates must belong to a common sub-category C3which is defined in terms of trivial truth value.As a schema is trivially true only if it is true,if names and ordinary predicates both belong to C3,it automatically follows that they both belong to C2.Thus to say that names and ordinary predicates do not both belong to the same sub-category C2to such an effect that (b*)does not obtain is not an option for Fara in the first place,given her ARG.As(b*)may come out false either because BCC schemata for names and those for ordinary predicates may differ in terms of their actual truth values,or simply because BCC schemata for names and those for ordinary predicates may differ in terms of whether they actually have any truth values at all,and as BCC schemata for ordinary predicates usually do have truth values,the most sensible option left for Fara to reject(b*)is to maintain that BCC schemata for names do not have any truth values at all.And the most straightforward way for those schemata for names to fail to have any truth values is by being ungrammatical,particularly ungrammatical to have names complimenting the appellative ‘being called’.But that is obviously inconsistent with Fara’s assumption CAT.

    Alternatively,Fara may locate the root of the differences in the calling relation itself,by exploiting some kind of equivocation.So she may argue that the calling relation applied to names is somewhat different from that applied to ordinary predicates.But that is inconsistent with her non-equivocation assumption NE,the assumption that the appellative calling relation is non-equivocal in its applications to proper names and typical predicates.Similarly as the considerations presented in the last two paragraphs,Fara may attempt to escape inconsistency by maintaining that NE requires non-equivocation in one sense,while to reject (b*)she only needs to concede equivocation in a different sense.But if we don’t lose sight of Fara’s ARG,particularly its premise(b),and the fact that trivial truth implies truth,we should remember that appealing to any equivocation giving rise to the differences of actual truth values of BCC schemata for names and those for ordinary predicates is not an option for Fara.For such an equivocation is impossible—it exists when it comes to actual truth values but does not exist when it comes to actual trivial truth values.The sensible option left for her is to concede that(b*)involves an equivocation in terms not of things which determine the schemata’s actual truth values but of whether the appellative calling relation can be applied to proper names and typical predicates that occur in the schemata to ensure that they have any truth value at all.And that would contradict Fara’s non-equivocation assumption NE.

    4 Back to Triviality

    Or,as a last resolve,Fara may tentatively contend that there is a certain sort of differenceDbetween proper names and other predicates,such that the existence ofDisnot enoughto undermine the analogy argument,butwell enoughto support different treatments of (b)and (b*),and to generate the significant differences ofauthority,fact and wording.Whether such a tricky difference can be successfully identified is an open question I’m not in a position to determine.It suffices for our purpose here to point out that such a move in turn only threatens the legitimacy of the ARG argument from the non-triviality of BCC schemata for typical predicates to that for proper names.If names and other predicates are indeed different in terms ofD,it would be unclear whether such a difference leads to vital triviality differences.

    So it takes more than the mere non-triviality of BCC schemata for typical predicates to prove that BCC for proper names is non-trivial.The straightforward,and more promising,way to show the non-triviality of BCC for names is rather to make explicit the semantic contents of its average instances and demonstrate that those instances themselves are non-trivial.Here is an instance of BCC for names,

    (5)‘Quine’is true of Willard just in case he is called Quine.

    To make explicit the content of it,we have to make explicit the content of ‘he is called Quine’.Fara suggested that this could be given in parallel to that regarding other predicates.([3])So for instance,

    (6)‘Willard is called stupid’is true just in case that something is done which entails that Willard∈[[‘stupid’]].

    Similarly,

    (7)‘Willard is called Quine’is true just in case that something is done which entails that Willard∈[[‘Quine’]].3[[‘stupid’]]is the set of things which have the property of being stupid,and[[‘Quine’]]is the set of things which have‘Quine’as a name.In her([4]),Fara offered a different semantic analysis which says that ‘x calls y F just in case x does something that entails or presupposes that y is F.But nothing hinges on this difference for our argument here.

    But again,there is a vital difference.Mentioning‘stupid’on the right hand side is sufficient,but not necessary,for explicating the content of‘Willard is called stupid’.For if something is done which entails that Willard∈[[‘dim-witted and ignorant’]],‘Willard is called stupid’ would be equally true.But mentioning the name ‘Quine’on the right hand side is not only sufficient,butnecessary,for explicating the content of‘Willard is called Quine’.It is utterly false that if something is done which entails that,say,Willard∈[[‘stupid’]],then‘Willard is called Quine’is true.Mentioning the name itself is very much essential.So what(5)really says is that

    (5′)‘Quine’is true of Willard just in case that something is done which entails that Willard∈[[‘Quine’]].

    Or more straightforwardly,

    (5′′)‘Quine’is true of Willard just in case that something is done which entails that Willard is someone who has‘Quine’as a name.

    But here it hasgone metalinguistic! Plainly,it is hard to see how that can be essentially different from Burge’s metalinguistic proposal,which Fara rejects,that

    (5′′′)‘Quine’is true of Willard just in case Willard was given the name‘Quine’in an appropriate way.

    Both,I suppose,are very close to run afoul of the Kripken criterion of non-triviality.Fara’s nonmetalinguistic Predicativism,so it seems,is no better off than its metalinguistic rivals.And if metalinguistic Predicativism really falls prey to Kripken triviality,then we have a good reason to reject not only Fara’s particular version of it,but perhaps the entire project of Predicativism itself.

    国产精品亚洲av一区麻豆| 亚洲av片天天在线观看| 国产精品一区二区精品视频观看| 久久久久亚洲av毛片大全| 美女高潮喷水抽搐中文字幕| 国产精华一区二区三区| 国产亚洲欧美精品永久| 超碰成人久久| 国产亚洲精品第一综合不卡| 99国产综合亚洲精品| 一进一出抽搐动态| 男男h啪啪无遮挡| 国产一区二区三区视频了| 国产精品久久久人人做人人爽| 亚洲七黄色美女视频| 亚洲人成伊人成综合网2020| 亚洲国产日韩欧美精品在线观看 | 亚洲国产欧美日韩在线播放| 亚洲av成人av| 99香蕉大伊视频| av天堂久久9| 老熟妇乱子伦视频在线观看| 婷婷六月久久综合丁香| 中国美女看黄片| 亚洲国产中文字幕在线视频| 国产精品99久久99久久久不卡| 一级a爱片免费观看的视频| av在线天堂中文字幕| 黄色片一级片一级黄色片| 国产av一区在线观看免费| 岛国在线观看网站| 免费少妇av软件| 久久精品人人爽人人爽视色| av超薄肉色丝袜交足视频| 视频区欧美日本亚洲| 悠悠久久av| 亚洲 国产 在线| 中文字幕人成人乱码亚洲影| 一进一出好大好爽视频| 国产成年人精品一区二区| 国产精品日韩av在线免费观看 | 色尼玛亚洲综合影院| 丰满人妻熟妇乱又伦精品不卡| 啦啦啦观看免费观看视频高清 | www.999成人在线观看| 露出奶头的视频| 18禁美女被吸乳视频| 麻豆av在线久日| 99在线视频只有这里精品首页| 两人在一起打扑克的视频| 国产人伦9x9x在线观看| 91九色精品人成在线观看| 国产精品免费视频内射| 国产野战对白在线观看| 国产精品久久久久久精品电影 | 欧美另类亚洲清纯唯美| 亚洲五月色婷婷综合| 久热这里只有精品99| 69av精品久久久久久| 狂野欧美激情性xxxx| 午夜福利影视在线免费观看| 精品人妻1区二区| 国产精品爽爽va在线观看网站 | 老司机福利观看| 欧美日韩瑟瑟在线播放| 久久精品国产清高在天天线| 久9热在线精品视频| 国产aⅴ精品一区二区三区波| 亚洲欧洲精品一区二区精品久久久| 黄色视频不卡| 久久天堂一区二区三区四区| 国产精品久久久人人做人人爽| 国产精品一区二区三区四区久久 | 精品一区二区三区视频在线观看免费| 欧美日韩黄片免| 亚洲一区二区三区色噜噜| 亚洲全国av大片| 中文字幕人成人乱码亚洲影| 亚洲av美国av| 国产av精品麻豆| 久久精品91无色码中文字幕| 99riav亚洲国产免费| 亚洲一卡2卡3卡4卡5卡精品中文| 精品国产国语对白av| 人人妻人人澡欧美一区二区 | av免费在线观看网站| 欧美黑人精品巨大| 男女下面插进去视频免费观看| 三级毛片av免费| 中出人妻视频一区二区| 精品国产国语对白av| 女同久久另类99精品国产91| 91成人精品电影| 亚洲一区中文字幕在线| 国产视频一区二区在线看| 国产av在哪里看| 国产av一区二区精品久久| 90打野战视频偷拍视频| 国产高清有码在线观看视频 | 熟女少妇亚洲综合色aaa.| 久久久久久久久免费视频了| 国产免费男女视频| 女同久久另类99精品国产91| 纯流量卡能插随身wifi吗| 精品久久久久久,| 精品国产美女av久久久久小说| 成人免费观看视频高清| 69av精品久久久久久| 久9热在线精品视频| 久久草成人影院| 免费在线观看日本一区| www日本在线高清视频| 亚洲电影在线观看av| 巨乳人妻的诱惑在线观看| 在线天堂中文资源库| 免费看美女性在线毛片视频| 久久午夜亚洲精品久久| 人妻久久中文字幕网| 国产成人免费无遮挡视频| 欧美日韩瑟瑟在线播放| 人人妻,人人澡人人爽秒播| 99re在线观看精品视频| 国产精品爽爽va在线观看网站 | 男人舔女人的私密视频| 国产xxxxx性猛交| 亚洲男人天堂网一区| 大陆偷拍与自拍| 成年人黄色毛片网站| 色综合欧美亚洲国产小说| 亚洲 欧美一区二区三区| 成人国产综合亚洲| 91字幕亚洲| 在线免费观看的www视频| 久久人妻熟女aⅴ| 日韩有码中文字幕| 法律面前人人平等表现在哪些方面| 香蕉久久夜色| 一进一出好大好爽视频| 非洲黑人性xxxx精品又粗又长| 国产亚洲精品av在线| 国产xxxxx性猛交| 日韩高清综合在线| 国产伦一二天堂av在线观看| 日韩欧美一区视频在线观看| 禁无遮挡网站| 久久精品亚洲熟妇少妇任你| 国产欧美日韩精品亚洲av| 免费在线观看亚洲国产| 国产精品98久久久久久宅男小说| av有码第一页| 国产单亲对白刺激| 不卡av一区二区三区| 国产又爽黄色视频| 99精品久久久久人妻精品| 久久精品亚洲精品国产色婷小说| 99热只有精品国产| 中出人妻视频一区二区| 久久婷婷成人综合色麻豆| 久久久精品欧美日韩精品| 色综合欧美亚洲国产小说| 亚洲 欧美 日韩 在线 免费| 久久人妻熟女aⅴ| 国产精品一区二区在线不卡| 天天躁狠狠躁夜夜躁狠狠躁| 国产av又大| 在线国产一区二区在线| 精品乱码久久久久久99久播| 性欧美人与动物交配| 在线观看66精品国产| 国产一区二区激情短视频| 久久精品国产99精品国产亚洲性色 | 久久国产精品影院| 长腿黑丝高跟| 午夜久久久在线观看| 亚洲一区二区三区色噜噜| 久久人妻福利社区极品人妻图片| 一级毛片女人18水好多| avwww免费| 午夜免费激情av| 国产精品 欧美亚洲| 咕卡用的链子| 国产亚洲精品久久久久久毛片| av欧美777| 国产av精品麻豆| 国产麻豆成人av免费视频| 91大片在线观看| 国产精品99久久99久久久不卡| 巨乳人妻的诱惑在线观看| 成人亚洲精品一区在线观看| 可以在线观看的亚洲视频| 久久国产精品人妻蜜桃| 精品少妇一区二区三区视频日本电影| 啦啦啦免费观看视频1| 免费人成视频x8x8入口观看| 大码成人一级视频| 亚洲av五月六月丁香网| 精品人妻1区二区| 少妇裸体淫交视频免费看高清 | 一级a爱视频在线免费观看| 亚洲va日本ⅴa欧美va伊人久久| 亚洲国产欧美日韩在线播放| 一级a爱片免费观看的视频| 国产成人精品久久二区二区91| 欧美日韩亚洲国产一区二区在线观看| 91九色精品人成在线观看| 一区二区三区高清视频在线| 岛国视频午夜一区免费看| 久久精品成人免费网站| 日韩欧美在线二视频| 免费观看精品视频网站| 真人做人爱边吃奶动态| 一本综合久久免费| 欧美不卡视频在线免费观看 | 欧美色欧美亚洲另类二区 | 国产精品1区2区在线观看.| 免费在线观看影片大全网站| 变态另类丝袜制服| 操出白浆在线播放| 久久 成人 亚洲| 999久久久精品免费观看国产| 日韩欧美一区二区三区在线观看| 高清毛片免费观看视频网站| 久久人人爽av亚洲精品天堂| 99久久久亚洲精品蜜臀av| 国产成年人精品一区二区| 99国产综合亚洲精品| 亚洲国产精品成人综合色| 午夜精品久久久久久毛片777| 制服人妻中文乱码| 免费无遮挡裸体视频| 欧美在线黄色| 又大又爽又粗| 国内精品久久久久精免费| 亚洲精品在线美女| 国产一区二区在线av高清观看| 国产麻豆成人av免费视频| 九色亚洲精品在线播放| 搡老妇女老女人老熟妇| 波多野结衣巨乳人妻| 久久婷婷人人爽人人干人人爱 | 国产野战对白在线观看| 操出白浆在线播放| 国产午夜福利久久久久久| 欧美日韩乱码在线| 色播在线永久视频| 亚洲av成人av| 九色国产91popny在线| 亚洲国产毛片av蜜桃av| 精品一区二区三区四区五区乱码| 亚洲 欧美 日韩 在线 免费| 日本a在线网址| 一级毛片精品| 亚洲久久久国产精品| 欧美一级毛片孕妇| 人人妻,人人澡人人爽秒播| 嫁个100分男人电影在线观看| 超碰成人久久| 俄罗斯特黄特色一大片| 99国产精品99久久久久| 91精品三级在线观看| 亚洲avbb在线观看| 亚洲成人精品中文字幕电影| 极品人妻少妇av视频| 亚洲欧美激情在线| av网站免费在线观看视频| 黑人操中国人逼视频| 午夜福利,免费看| 一卡2卡三卡四卡精品乱码亚洲| 日本免费一区二区三区高清不卡 | 12—13女人毛片做爰片一| av超薄肉色丝袜交足视频| 精品久久久精品久久久| 90打野战视频偷拍视频| 国产精品 欧美亚洲| 欧美激情久久久久久爽电影 | 国产高清视频在线播放一区| 亚洲av美国av| 老鸭窝网址在线观看| 制服人妻中文乱码| 国产av一区二区精品久久| 久久久久久亚洲精品国产蜜桃av| 乱人伦中国视频| 国产色视频综合| 曰老女人黄片| 国产高清有码在线观看视频 | 非洲黑人性xxxx精品又粗又长| 亚洲中文字幕日韩| 国产成人精品无人区| 精品高清国产在线一区| 亚洲熟妇熟女久久| 久久人妻av系列| av欧美777| 在线av久久热| 欧美日本亚洲视频在线播放| 99久久精品国产亚洲精品| 欧美亚洲日本最大视频资源| a在线观看视频网站| 亚洲一区中文字幕在线| 日日干狠狠操夜夜爽| 精品高清国产在线一区| www.999成人在线观看| 国产片内射在线| 99re在线观看精品视频| 91麻豆av在线| 在线视频色国产色| 国产区一区二久久| 人人妻人人澡欧美一区二区 | 日本欧美视频一区| 大码成人一级视频| 国产又爽黄色视频| 91麻豆av在线| 日韩 欧美 亚洲 中文字幕| 夜夜夜夜夜久久久久| 精品电影一区二区在线| 日本一区二区免费在线视频| 亚洲专区中文字幕在线| 日本一区二区免费在线视频| 亚洲全国av大片| 久久午夜亚洲精品久久| 亚洲精品中文字幕在线视频| 亚洲色图 男人天堂 中文字幕| 欧美成人午夜精品| 一边摸一边抽搐一进一小说| 久久久久国产精品人妻aⅴ院| 久久中文字幕一级| 中文字幕精品免费在线观看视频| 日本免费a在线| 在线国产一区二区在线| 亚洲狠狠婷婷综合久久图片| 一级毛片精品| avwww免费| 免费在线观看黄色视频的| 久久久久久久久中文| 免费少妇av软件| 免费看十八禁软件| 免费一级毛片在线播放高清视频 | 欧美中文日本在线观看视频| 欧美成人午夜精品| 国产精品九九99| 免费久久久久久久精品成人欧美视频| 妹子高潮喷水视频| 香蕉丝袜av| 国产精品一区二区在线不卡| 人人妻,人人澡人人爽秒播| 电影成人av| 真人做人爱边吃奶动态| 精品一品国产午夜福利视频| 久久香蕉激情| 亚洲av五月六月丁香网| 久久久水蜜桃国产精品网| 欧美日韩亚洲国产一区二区在线观看| 麻豆久久精品国产亚洲av| 国产精品一区二区三区四区久久 | 黑人操中国人逼视频| 久久亚洲精品不卡| 欧美日韩福利视频一区二区| 久久精品亚洲精品国产色婷小说| 午夜福利,免费看| 国产单亲对白刺激| 国产精品免费视频内射| 久久天堂一区二区三区四区| 桃红色精品国产亚洲av| 亚洲av成人一区二区三| 亚洲久久久国产精品| 女人被狂操c到高潮| 激情视频va一区二区三区| 黑丝袜美女国产一区| 国产aⅴ精品一区二区三区波| 99国产极品粉嫩在线观看| av超薄肉色丝袜交足视频| 国产亚洲精品av在线| 少妇被粗大的猛进出69影院| 国产国语露脸激情在线看| 一本大道久久a久久精品| 男女床上黄色一级片免费看| 国产区一区二久久| 亚洲精品在线美女| 两个人视频免费观看高清| 免费在线观看日本一区| av欧美777| 美女 人体艺术 gogo| 亚洲人成网站在线播放欧美日韩| 嫩草影院精品99| 日本三级黄在线观看| www.自偷自拍.com| 麻豆av在线久日| 亚洲国产日韩欧美精品在线观看 | 日本黄色视频三级网站网址| 欧美色视频一区免费| 在线观看www视频免费| 亚洲成av人片免费观看| 一进一出抽搐gif免费好疼| 国产欧美日韩综合在线一区二区| 日本五十路高清| 精品欧美国产一区二区三| 超碰成人久久| 国产精品日韩av在线免费观看 | 亚洲国产精品999在线| 在线观看免费日韩欧美大片| 亚洲专区字幕在线| 一二三四社区在线视频社区8| 亚洲精品国产一区二区精华液| 波多野结衣高清无吗| 欧美成人一区二区免费高清观看 | 国产精品美女特级片免费视频播放器 | 午夜视频精品福利| 日韩av在线大香蕉| netflix在线观看网站| 亚洲精品美女久久久久99蜜臀| 成熟少妇高潮喷水视频| 天天躁夜夜躁狠狠躁躁| 男女下面插进去视频免费观看| 高潮久久久久久久久久久不卡| 国产又爽黄色视频| 人人妻人人澡人人看| av免费在线观看网站| 精品国产乱码久久久久久男人| 啦啦啦观看免费观看视频高清 | 欧美中文综合在线视频| 国产在线观看jvid| 国产单亲对白刺激| av天堂在线播放| 如日韩欧美国产精品一区二区三区| 天天一区二区日本电影三级 | 看黄色毛片网站| 国产一卡二卡三卡精品| 午夜久久久在线观看| 亚洲精品在线观看二区| 国产欧美日韩一区二区精品| 中文亚洲av片在线观看爽| 国产精品精品国产色婷婷| 国产精品一区二区在线不卡| 久热这里只有精品99| 女人被狂操c到高潮| 午夜精品国产一区二区电影| 国产亚洲av嫩草精品影院| 亚洲国产日韩欧美精品在线观看 | 亚洲av电影在线进入| 免费在线观看亚洲国产| 两性午夜刺激爽爽歪歪视频在线观看 | 无遮挡黄片免费观看| 亚洲一码二码三码区别大吗| √禁漫天堂资源中文www| 精品国产亚洲在线| 一个人观看的视频www高清免费观看 | 精品一品国产午夜福利视频| 黄片播放在线免费| 国产三级黄色录像| 两性午夜刺激爽爽歪歪视频在线观看 | avwww免费| 国产日韩一区二区三区精品不卡| 视频区欧美日本亚洲| 免费在线观看视频国产中文字幕亚洲| 亚洲精品在线美女| 波多野结衣一区麻豆| 精品人妻1区二区| 色av中文字幕| 亚洲av美国av| 咕卡用的链子| 一级,二级,三级黄色视频| 妹子高潮喷水视频| 两人在一起打扑克的视频| 日韩 欧美 亚洲 中文字幕| 制服人妻中文乱码| 淫秽高清视频在线观看| 亚洲最大成人中文| 国产精华一区二区三区| 人人妻,人人澡人人爽秒播| 成熟少妇高潮喷水视频| 国产精品二区激情视频| 精品久久久精品久久久| 久久精品成人免费网站| 嫩草影视91久久| 成人三级做爰电影| 午夜福利,免费看| 国产亚洲精品综合一区在线观看 | 俄罗斯特黄特色一大片| 一级a爱视频在线免费观看| 国产熟女午夜一区二区三区| 久久久国产欧美日韩av| 高清在线国产一区| 欧美日韩中文字幕国产精品一区二区三区 | av中文乱码字幕在线| 国产精品久久电影中文字幕| 一二三四社区在线视频社区8| 在线观看舔阴道视频| 亚洲aⅴ乱码一区二区在线播放 | 国产精品亚洲一级av第二区| 国产国语露脸激情在线看| 啦啦啦免费观看视频1| 欧美久久黑人一区二区| 99国产综合亚洲精品| 国产精品免费视频内射| bbb黄色大片| 国产又色又爽无遮挡免费看| 中文字幕久久专区| 日本a在线网址| 激情视频va一区二区三区| 免费在线观看亚洲国产| 在线永久观看黄色视频| 国产成人免费无遮挡视频| 高清黄色对白视频在线免费看| 亚洲精品在线美女| 在线av久久热| 岛国视频午夜一区免费看| 黄色毛片三级朝国网站| 亚洲av日韩精品久久久久久密| 窝窝影院91人妻| 精品人妻在线不人妻| 操出白浆在线播放| 一本综合久久免费| 黄色 视频免费看| 在线天堂中文资源库| 免费久久久久久久精品成人欧美视频| 韩国精品一区二区三区| 在线观看免费日韩欧美大片| 欧美一级a爱片免费观看看 | 精品久久久久久久毛片微露脸| 老司机福利观看| 欧美日韩黄片免| 久久精品国产亚洲av高清一级| 在线观看舔阴道视频| 国产精品av久久久久免费| av电影中文网址| 久久人妻熟女aⅴ| 国产精品乱码一区二三区的特点 | 99国产精品一区二区三区| 搡老妇女老女人老熟妇| 激情在线观看视频在线高清| 国产精品久久视频播放| 日韩中文字幕欧美一区二区| 成年人黄色毛片网站| 女人被躁到高潮嗷嗷叫费观| 操出白浆在线播放| 国产av在哪里看| 国产成人欧美在线观看| 久久狼人影院| svipshipincom国产片| 欧美午夜高清在线| 50天的宝宝边吃奶边哭怎么回事| 19禁男女啪啪无遮挡网站| 国产成人免费无遮挡视频| 一个人免费在线观看的高清视频| 亚洲av成人一区二区三| 精品免费久久久久久久清纯| 精品福利观看| 丝袜人妻中文字幕| 欧美亚洲日本最大视频资源| 国产麻豆成人av免费视频| 日韩 欧美 亚洲 中文字幕| 日日夜夜操网爽| 亚洲一码二码三码区别大吗| ponron亚洲| 午夜成年电影在线免费观看| 国产成人精品在线电影| 国产亚洲av高清不卡| 亚洲成a人片在线一区二区| 1024香蕉在线观看| 女人爽到高潮嗷嗷叫在线视频| 日韩高清综合在线| 午夜福利18| 淫妇啪啪啪对白视频| 一夜夜www| 每晚都被弄得嗷嗷叫到高潮| 色综合欧美亚洲国产小说| 亚洲精品国产精品久久久不卡| 亚洲色图av天堂| 一进一出抽搐动态| 国产欧美日韩一区二区三| 久久精品国产综合久久久| 午夜福利视频1000在线观看 | 久久热在线av| 亚洲av第一区精品v没综合| 亚洲国产欧美日韩在线播放| 国产激情久久老熟女| 国产成人精品在线电影| 亚洲中文字幕日韩| 91麻豆av在线| av有码第一页| 女同久久另类99精品国产91| 国产精品亚洲av一区麻豆| 长腿黑丝高跟| 国产精品99久久99久久久不卡| 免费在线观看亚洲国产| 亚洲男人天堂网一区| 亚洲国产精品合色在线| 国产国语露脸激情在线看| 午夜免费观看网址| 日韩国内少妇激情av| 久久久国产成人免费| 久热这里只有精品99| 国产熟女xx| 国产熟女午夜一区二区三区| 欧美黑人精品巨大| 好看av亚洲va欧美ⅴa在| 真人一进一出gif抽搐免费| 国产不卡一卡二| 看片在线看免费视频| 99riav亚洲国产免费| 美女免费视频网站| 中文字幕高清在线视频| 在线观看免费日韩欧美大片| 99re在线观看精品视频| 丝袜美足系列| 91国产中文字幕| 日本欧美视频一区| 热re99久久国产66热| 久久性视频一级片| 日韩精品免费视频一区二区三区| 亚洲午夜理论影院| 真人一进一出gif抽搐免费| 久久精品aⅴ一区二区三区四区| 好看av亚洲va欧美ⅴa在| 69精品国产乱码久久久| 色综合亚洲欧美另类图片|