• <tr id="yyy80"></tr>
  • <sup id="yyy80"></sup>
  • <tfoot id="yyy80"><noscript id="yyy80"></noscript></tfoot>
  • 99热精品在线国产_美女午夜性视频免费_国产精品国产高清国产av_av欧美777_自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇_亚洲熟女精品中文字幕_www日本黄色视频网_国产精品野战在线观看 ?

    Lumping and Grounding:A Critical Defence of Premise Semantics for Counterfactuals

    2017-06-05 14:59:58DuenMinDeng
    邏輯學(xué)研究 2017年1期
    關(guān)鍵詞:條件句語義學(xué)命題

    Duen-Min Deng

    Department of Philosophy,National Taiwan University

    dmdeng@ntu.edu.tw

    Lumping and Grounding:A Critical Defence of Premise Semantics for Counterfactuals

    Duen-Min Deng

    Department of Philosophy,National Taiwan University

    dmdeng@ntu.edu.tw

    .The basic idea of premise semantics is roughly this:A counterfactual conditional asserts that its consequent follows from its antecedent when we add some suitable premises. To make it a viable analysis,Kratzer(1981,1989)introduces the notion of‘premise sets’representing suitable ways of adding premises,such that‘p□→q’is true iff every premise set is a subset of some premise set that logically implies the consequent q.The project,then,is to find appropriate constraints on premise sets that can give us the correct truth-conditions for counterfactuals.

    Kratzer(1989)proposes invoking the notion of‘lumping’to specify the required constraints on premise sets.The idea is that propositions are sometimes‘lumped’together,such that when we add one proposition in our counterfactual reasoning we will thereby add all the propositions it lumps.The lumping relation is then defined under the framework of a situation semantics by some part-whole relation on situations.This approach has the advantage of being able to solve many problems that Kratzer’s previous accounts encounter.But it also suffers from enormous difficulties,as Kanazawa et al.(2005)show in their triviality results.Kratzer herselfalsoabandonedthisapproachverysoon(Kratzer1990,2002),reformulatingherpremise semantics in terms of the notion of‘natural’propositions instead of the lumping relations on propositions.

    In this paper,I will offer a critical defence of Kratzer’s‘lumping’semantics in her 1989 version.My proposal is that we understand the notion of lumping in terms of the notion of‘grounding’instead of the part-whole relations on situations.More precisely,on my proposal a proposition p lumps a proposition q if and only if p is grounded in q,and accordingly,when we add a proposition into a counterfactual scenario we will thereby add all the propositions that are its grounds.In this way,I argue,we can accommodate all the examples that motivate the lumping semantics,whilst avoiding the triviality results of Kanazawa et al.(2005).

    1 Premise Semantics and Its Motivations

    Thebasicideaofpremisesemanticsisroughlythis:Acounterfactualconditional asserts that its consequent follows from its antecedent with some suitable premises. For instance,we think that the counterfactual conditional‘If the match had been scratched,it would have lighted’asserts something true,because we think that the match’s lighting follows logically from its being scratched with some suitable premises,including some background facts about the match and the laws of nature thatgovern it.This idea is intuitively plausible.The problem is that we still need to specify what count as‘suitable’premises to be added in our counterfactual reasoning.

    Quite naturally,the premises to be added in our counterfactual reasoning should berequiredtobetrueinourworldandcompatiblewiththeantecedent.Butinaddition tothesetwoconstraints,whatelseshouldwerequireoftheaddedpremisestobecount as suitable?An early attempt to answer this question was proposed by Goodman in [3].On this view,besides truth and compatibility with the antecedent,the added premises are required also to be cotenable with the antecedent,in the sense that they should not be those propositions that could be false if the antecedent were true.1In fact,Goodman’s definition states that q is cotenable with p iff it is not the case that q would not be true if p were.([3],p.15)This amounts to saying that q is cotenable with p iff~(p□→~q), which is equivalent to p?→q.However,we have reason to think that something stronger is required for cotenability.For even if q might be true if p were,it could still be the case q might be false if p were.In such cases,we are still not justified in adding q in our counterfactual reasoning.So I here take a slightly different definition from Goodman’s:On my definition,q is cotenable with p iff it is not the case that q might be false if p were,i.e.,~(p?→~q),which is equivalent to p□→q.For suppose the added premises might be false if the antecedent were true,we would no longer regard the counterfactual as asserting something true simply on the basis that its antecedent plus the added premises logically imply its consequent.So,it is plausible to exclude propositions not cotenable with the antecedent from the added premises.

    For instance,consider the following counterfactual conditional:

    (1)If Boris had gone to the party,he would have met Olga there.

    Suppose that Boris did not come to the party but Olga did,and suppose that the party wassmall,suchthatallpeopleinthepartymeteachother.Thefollowingpropositions are thus true:

    (2) a.Boris was not in the party.

    b.Olga was in the party.

    c.All people in the party met each other.

    Based on this information,we naturally regard(1)as true because its consequent follows logically from its antecedent together with the true premises(2b)and(2c). However,suppose Olga wanted to avoid Boris.In this case,we would no longer regard(1)as true.Even if Boris had gone to the party,he would not have met Olga there,for she would not have been in the party if Boris had gone there.In Goodman’s term,(2b)is not cotenable with the antecedent of(1),and hence should be excluded from the premises to be added in our evaluation of(1).

    Now,apremisesemanticsbasedonGoodman’saccountcanbeformalisedasfollows.2The formalisation is reconstructed based on Kratzer’s semantics and the terminology used in[5]to facilitate our discussions.To evaluate any counterfactual conditional,our conversational context shouldprovide us with a set F of true propositions relevant for our evaluation.Call such a set F a base set.(In the above example,the base set in our context should include at least 2a,2b,and 2c.)To evaluate whether a counterfactual conditional is true(relative to a base set),we add propositions from the base set F to our premises to see whether they, together with the antecedent,should logically imply the consequent.On Goodman’s account,the added propositions are required to be cotenable with the antecedent.We maythusdefineaGoodmanpremiseset,whichissupposedtorepresentanysuchway ofaddingpropositionsmeetingthecotenabilityconstrainttoourpremises,asfollows.

    The Goodman Crucial Set and Premise Sets

    Let F be a base set provided by the context,and p be a proposition. We define GF,p,called the Goodman crucial set,as the set of all subsets A of F∪{p}satisfying the following conditions:

    Intuitively,acounterfactualconditionalistrueifitsconsequentfollowslogicallyfrom the maximal premise sets—i.e.,if its consequent follows when we add as many suitable premises as consistency allows to its antecedent.But such a characterisation would require the existence of maximal premise sets,which for some technical reason we are not guaranteed to have.As a remedy,we may formulate it instead by saying that a counterfactual is true iff every premise set can be extended to a premise set that logically imply the consequent.So we have the following truth-conditions for Goodman’s premise semantics.

    Goodman’s premise semantics

    Let F be a base set provided by the context.Then a counterfactual conditional p□→q is true(in this context)if and only if for every A in GF,p,there is some B in GF,psuch that A?B and B logically implies q.

    However,this premise semantics is utterly unsatisfactory,as Goodman himself notices.For in order to apply it to evaluate whether p□→q is true,we need to determine first which propositions in the base set are cotenable with p(so as to determine the Goodman crucial set).But to determine which propositions in the base set are cotenable with p,we need to evaluate the truth or falsity of some counterfactual conditionals again.For according to our definition,any proposition r is said to be cotenable with p if and only if it is not the case that r might be false if p were true, or equivalently,iff p□→r is true.But to evaluate whether p□→r is true on this semantics,we again need to know which propositions in the base set are cotenable withp.So we are led to an infinite regress or a circle,and can never apply this semantics to evaluate any counterfactual conditional.

    Such a‘cotenability’problem is well-known.One common response is to suggest that we abandon premise semantics and try something else.So an alternative semantics was developed by Lewis and Stalnaker,the central idea of which is to invoke a set of entities called possible worlds,together with a system of ordering imposed on it.On this view,a counterfactual conditional p□→q is true in a world w if and only if some world where p and q are both true is closer to w(according to the ordering system)than any world where p is true but q is false.Which world is closer to w will then be determined by their overall similarity to w.

    So how does the possible-worlds semantics as developed by Lewis and Stalnaker avoid the‘cotenability’problem that confronts Goodman’s semantics?As we have seen,the root of the problem is that in Goodman’s semantics the truthconditions we provide for counterfactuals directly rely on something about the truth or falsity of counterfactuals,thus rendering it regressive or circular.Now,in Lewis and Stalnaker’s semantics,the truth-conditions are specified in terms of the similarities amongst possible worlds,which do not directly involve the truth or falsity of counterfactuals.This avoids the‘cotenability’problem,but still faces difficulties. For in order for the semantics to yield the correct predictions,the invoked notion of‘similarity’must be a technical one quite unlike our intuitive idea of similarity.But what can that be?Lewis in[10]has attempted a rather complicated story about how to measure the similarities amongst worlds to get the truth-conditions of counterfactualsright,but manyremainscepticalandunsatisfied.Duetothelimitedspacehere,I cannot go through the details of Lewis’s story and its difficulties,which have already been much discussed in the literature.But I would just mention one case against Lewis that will be relevant to our discussions below,which was raised in[5].

    Suppose a zebra escaped from the Hamburg zoo due to a forgetful keeper who forgottoclosethedoorofacompoundcontainingzebras,giraffes,andgazelles.Now, consider the following counterfactual conditionals:

    (3)If a different animal had escaped instead,it would have been a zebra.

    (4)If a different animal had escaped instead,it might have been a gazelle.

    Intuitively,(3)is false and(4)is true in our context,but it is difficult to see how Lewis’saccountcanaccommodatethiswithastoryaboutsimilaritiesamongstworlds. For in the actual world it is a zebra that escaped,and so intuitively,a world where the escaping animal was a different zebra should be more similar to the actual world than aworldwheretheescapinganimalwasofadifferentspecies.Ifso,Lewis’ssemantics should predict that(3)is true and(4)is false,which seems wrong.To make the right prediction,we should have a notion of‘similarity’on which the apparent similarities with the actual escaping zebra do not count.But it is very difficult to see what such a notion of‘similarity’can be:‘It must then be a very special sort of similarity’([5],p.626).

    The zebra case therefore presents a difficulty for Lewis’s semantics.We need an explanation,absent in Lewis’s account,of why similarity with the actual zebra should not count in evaluating such counterfactuals like(3)and(4).It is somehow striking to note that Goodman’s semantics can nevertheless offer some explanation.We can explainwhyinevaluating(3)and(4),wedonot holdfixedtheactual propertiesofthe escaping animal in our counterfactual scenarios.For in evaluating(3)and(4),such propositions that describe the actual features of the escaping animal are not allowed to be added to our premises:

    (5) a.The animal that escaped was striped.

    b.The animal that escaped was black and white.

    c.The animal that escaped was a zebra.

    ……

    The reason is that these propositions are not contenable with the antecedent of(3)and (4),in the sense that they could fail to be true if the antecedent were true.That is to say,the following seem true:

    (6) a.If a different animal had escaped instead,it might not have been striped.

    b.If a different animal had escaped instead,it might not have been black andwhite.

    c.If a different animal had escaped instead,it might not have been a zebra.

    ……

    This explains why in evaluating(3)and(4),we do not hold fixed the actual features of the escaping animal,as they are not cotenable with our counterfactual supposition.

    Such an explanation,of course,is not completely satisfactory due to the cotenability problem.For to say that(5c)is not cotenable with the antecedent,according to our definition,is just to say that(6c)is true,which is equivalent to saying that(3)is false.Here the circularity is quite obvious.However,if we can have an explanation for why such propositions like(5c)should be excluded from the added premises without relying on our intuitions about counterfactuals,it seems that we can still have a defensible approach.Kratzer offered one such account in[5],which invokes the notion of‘lumping’instead of the problematic idea of cotenability.The idea is that propositions are sometimes‘lumped’together,such that when we add one proposition in our counterfactual reasoning we will thereby add all the propositions it lumps. In this way,(5c)can be excluded from the added premises,not because it is not cotenable with the antecedent,but because it lumps some propositions incompatible with the antecedent.The detail of this account will be examined in the next section.

    2 Lumping and Its Formality

    Intheprevioussection,wehaveexplainedthebasicideaofpremisesemantics:a counterfactual conditional is true if and only if its consequent follows logically from its antecedent with some suitable premises.Intuitively,the suitable premises to be added in our counterfactual reasoning are required to be true in our world and compatiblewiththeantecedent.Butinadditiontothesetworequirements,thereshouldbe some more constraints.We have seen that Goodman tried to capture the constraints by requiring the added premises to be‘cotenable’:they should in some way remain true in our counterfactual scenarios.But the difficulty is that we seem to have no non-circular specification of cotenability without relying on the very notion of counterfactual conditionals.

    Ifcotenabilityfailstocapturetherequiredconstraints,whatelsecando?Kratzer in[5]proposes invoking the idea of‘lumping’to capture the constraints.The basic idea is that propositions are sometimes lumped together,such that when we add one proposition to our premises we will thereby add all the propositions it lumps.As a result,some propositions may be true in our world and compatible with the antecedent, yet are unsuitable for being added in our premises because they lump some other propositions that will contradict the antecedent.

    To characterise the notion of lumping formally,Kratzer appeals to a situation semantics.The idea is that propositions can be true or false not only in possible worlds,butalsoinpartsofpossibleworlds,whichshecalls‘situations’.Situationsare partsofpossibleworldswithacertainmereologicalstructure:somesituationsmaybe parts of larger situations,and some situations may contain smaller situations as parts. Situations that are thus related by the part-whole relation are not wholly distinct,and hence the corresponding propositions are in some sense‘lumped’together according to the mereological structure of the situations.So if we identify a proposition,not as a setofpossibleworlds,butasasetofpossiblesituations(i.e.,partsofpossibleworlds) in which it is true,we may define a lumping relationship based on the mereological structure of the possible situations.For instance,suppose Paula painted a still life by painting some apples and some bananas.The situation in which Paula was painting the apples is therefore contained as a part of the larger situation in which Paula was painting the still life.In this sense,we may say the proposition that Paula painted a still life lumps(in our world)the proposition that Paula painted apples,and thus in adding the former to our premises we will in some sense also add the latter as a part. To capture this formally,Kratzer offers the following definition([5],p.611):

    Lumping

    A proposition p lumps a proposition q in a world w if and only if(i) and(ii)both hold:

    (i)p is true in w.

    (ii)Whenever a situation s is part of w and p is true in s,then q is true in s as well.

    So,inourexample,thepropositionthatPaulapaintedastilllifelumpstheproposition that Paula painted apples in our world,for they are true in our world,and the actual situationofourworldwherePaulawaspaintingastilllifecontainsthesituationwhere Paula was painting apples as a part,hence also makes the latter proposition true.

    The idea of lumping also provides a nice explanation for our intuitions in the zebra example.Recall that in the zebra case,we intuitively think that the actual features of the escaping zebra should be irrelevant in considering the counterfactual scenario where a different animal had escaped.So we need an explanation for why in so conceiving,we should not add any of such propositions as:

    (5) a.The animal that escaped was striped.

    b.The animal that escaped was black and white.

    c.The animal that escaped was a zebra.

    ……

    We now have a nice explanation in terms of lumping.Suppose the zebra that actually escaped was named‘John’.Then we can show that each of the propositions listed above lumps the propositions that John escaped,for what makes any of these propositions true in our world is supposed to be the actual situation where John escaped from the zoo.This explains why we should not add these propositions,for they lump the proposition that John escaped,which contradicts the counterfactual supposition.

    With the notion of lumping in hand,Kratzer then offers a premise semantics accordingly.The idea,again,is that we define‘premise sets’to represent suitable ways of adding propositions to our premises,and then use the set of premise sets to provide truth-conditions for counterfactual conditionals.3See([5],p.635).Here I make some slight modification to fit our discussions.

    The Kratzer Crucial Set and Premise Sets

    Let F be a base set provided by the context,and p be a proposition. We define KF,p,called the Kratzer crucial set,as the set of all subsets A of F∪{p}satisfying the following conditions:

    (i)A is consistent;

    (ii)p∈A;

    (iii)A is closed under lumping;i.e.,for any q,r∈F,if q∈A and q lumps r in our world,then r∈A;

    (iv)*A is closed under logical consequence;i.e.,for any B?A and any q∈F,if B logically implies q,then q∈A.4The requirement of closure under logical consequence may appear to be questionable,and it does lead to some problems(see[4]and the discussions in the next section).Kratzer’s main motivation for making this requirement is to deal with the King Ludwig case(see[5],p.640f).However,her treatment there is still not completely satisfactory.This eventually led Kratzer to remove this logical closure requirement in her 2012 reprinted version of the paper and tried an alternative treatment of the King Ludwig case(see[7],pp.133,143f).

    Any such set A in KF,pis called a Kratzer premise set.

    Kratzer’s premise semantics

    Let F be a base set provided by the context.Then a counterfactual conditional p□→q is true(in this context)if and only if for every A∈KF,p,there is some B∈KF,psuch that A?B and B logically implies q.

    Let us use an example to see how the semantics works.5See([5],p.628).NoticethatIhavemadesomeslightmodificationsofthecasetofitmydiscussions here.Suppose Paula and Otto are the only persons in this room,and they are both painters.Suppose Clara is a sculptor,not a painter.So our base set should contain(at least)the following propositions:

    (7) a.Paula is in this room.

    b.Otto is in this room.

    c.Paula and Otto are the only persons in this room.

    d.All persons in this room are painters.

    e.Clara is not a painter.

    Now,consider the following counterfactuals:

    (8)If Clara were also in this room,she would(still)not be a painter.

    (9)If Clara were also in this room,she might be a painter.

    Here the antecedent of the counterfactuals is this:

    (10)Clara is in this room.

    Intuitively,(8)is true and(9)is false.But presumably,any set that contains(10)and (7d)will have no consistent superset that logically implies that Clara is not a painter. So if we are to make the correct prediction,we should exclude(7d)from being added to our premise sets.Kratzer’s lumping semantics can explain this.For arguably,(7d) is true in all and only those actual situations that contain this room as a part,and(7a), (7b),and(7c)are all true in all these situations.So,arguably,(7d)lumps(7a),(7b), and(7c)in our world.But(7a),(7b),and(7c)form a set that is inconsistent with our antecedent(10),and hence no Kratzer premise set should include(7d),lest it lump propositions inconsistent with our antecedent.

    So,what should Kratzer’s lumping semantics predict about(8)and(9)?As we have explained,(7d)lumps(7a),(7b),and(7c)in our world,and hence should not be included in any premise set.For similar reasons,(7c)lumps(7a)and(7b)in ourworld,and should not be included in any premise set either.But no further lumping relationship holds amongst these propositions.So,presumably,all the propositions listed in(7)except(7c)and(7d)can be added to our premise sets,and hence every premise set can be extended to a larger premise set that includes(7e).As a result,(8) is true and(9)is false according to Kratzer’s semantics.

    Now,compare this with another case(see[3],p.37).Suppose again that Paula and Otto are the only persons in this room,and suppose that everyone in this room is safe from freezing.Consider a certain Eskimo,say Eason,who is at this moment nearly frozen to death somewhere in the Arctic.Intuitively,we should regard the following counterfactual as true:

    (11)If Eason were now in this room,he would be safe from freezing.

    The case appears to be structurally similar to the previous one.Our base set includes (at least)the following propositions:

    (12) a.Paula is in this room.

    b.Otto is in this room.

    c.Paula and Otto are the only persons in this room.

    d.All persons in this room are safe from freezing.

    e.Eason is nearly frozen to death.

    Now if the case is really the same as the previous one,we might similarly expect that (12d)should lump(12a),(12b)and(12c),and hence should be unsuitable for being added in any Kratzer premise set on pain of inconsistency.But then,the semantics would predict(11)to be false,which is contrary to our intuition.

    To deal with such cases like this,Kratzer suggests making a distinction between two readings of a universally quantified sentence(see[5],pp.620ff).Roughly speaking,on an accidental reading,a universally quantified sentence‘All Fs are G’is true inasituationsonlyifsisbigenoughtocontaintheF-situations.Onanon-accidental reading,by contrast,‘All Fs are G’is true in all or none of the situations of a world. This is meant to capture the idea that a non-accidental generalisation asserts some genuine connection on a generic level,and hence should be true everywhere in the world if true at all.So if we take an accidental reading,(12d)is true in all and only those actual situations that contain this room as a part.Since(12a),(12b)and(12c) are all true in these situations,they are indeed lumped by(12d)on such an accidental reading.However,if we understand(12d)as a non-accidental generalisation(which seems more natural here),it should be true in all situations of the actual world.As a result,(12d)on this reading lumps no other propositions in our list according to our definition of lumping,but is lumped by each of them instead.Consequently,each Kratzer premise set that contains any proposition in the list should also contain(12d). But(12d)together with the antecedent of(11)logically implies that Eason is safe from freezing.As a result,(11)is true according to Kratzer’s semantics,which agreeswith our intuition.

    Kratzer’s distinction between accidental and non-accidental readings is intended to capture the idea that in considering a counterfactual scenario we usually hold the laws of nature fixed.Whereas Goodman explains this idea in terms of cotenability (i.e.,that the laws of nature are usually cotenable with our counterfactual suppositions),Kratzer explains it in terms of lumping(i.e.,that the laws are non-accidental generalisationswhichlumpveryfewpropositionsbutarelumpedbyeverytrueproposition).We usually can bring lawlike generalisations into counterfactual scenarios because they usually lumps nothing that will contradict the counterfactual suppositions.We usually do bring lawlike generalisations into counterfactual scenarios because they are lumped by every true proposition,such that in adding any proposition at all we thereby also add the lawlike generalisations it lumps.In this way,the roles that laws of nature are supposed to play in our counterfactual reasoning can be nicely explained by their lumping features.

    Kratzer’s‘lumping’semantics therefore presents a promising approach to work out the idea of premise semantics whilst avoiding the problems confronting Goodman’s account.But there may still be some worries.In the next section,I will briefly examine a problem presented in[4],and then raise my own worries about lumping.

    3 Worries about the Lumping Semantics

    In[4],some‘triviality’resultsarepresentedbyKanazawatoshowthatKratzer’s semantics fails to rule out certain problematic cases that would collapse the truthconditions of counterfactuals to triviality.The problematic cases are roughly as follows.

    Consider the tautologous proposition T that is true in all possible worlds but in no situations strictly smaller than a world.Consider also the‘world-proposition’pwthat is true in w and in no other world.Now,suppose w is our actual world.Certainly, both T and pware true propositions in our world.If our base set contains T and pwas relevant propositions,then it can be shown that Kratzer’s truth-conditions would collapse to triviality.For consider a counterfactual q□→r,where q is in fact false in our world w.Then there will be no Kratzer premise set at all that satisfies the constraints Kratzer demands.Recall that a Kratzer premise set A for this counterfactual is supposed to meet the following conditions:

    (i)A is consistent;

    (ii)q∈A;

    (iii)A is closed under lumping;i.e.,for any p1,p2∈F,if p1∈A and p1lumps p2in our world,then p2∈A;

    (iv)A is closed under logical consequence;i.e.,for any B?A and any p∈F,if B logically implies p,then p∈A.Now,since T is tautologous,T is logically implied by any set,the empty set included. So by(iv),we should have T∈A.But since T is true in no situations but worlds,T lumps pwin our world w because pwis true in the only situation of w where T is true. But then,by(iii),we should have pw∈A.However,by(ii)we also have q∈A.But there is no world in which both pwand q are true(because pwis true in w and in no other world,and q is false in w).This contradicts(i).As a result,there is no Kratzer premise set that satisfies all the constraints(i)–(iv),and consequently,Krazter’s truthconditions for counterfactuals in terms of Kratzer premise sets collapse to triviality.

    To this triviality result,it can be replied that the proposition pwin question is highly dubious,and hence no conversational context would include it as a relevant proposition in our base set.But Kanazawa et al.have a second triviality case that invokes no such proposition.Again,consider the counterfactual q□→r,where q is in fact false in our world w.Accordingly,both~q and q∨~q are true in our world w.Now,if our base set contains these two propositions(i.e.,~q and q∨~q) as relevant propositions,then it can be shown again that Kratzer’s truth-conditions would collapse to triviality.For arguably,the disjunctive proposition q∨~q lumps~q in our world w(because what makes the disjunction true in the actual world is the situation where~q is true).So for any putative Kratzer premise set A,by the fourth condition(iv),the tautology q∨~q should be in A;but then we should have~q∈A by the condition(iii)about closure under lumping.As a result,A should contain both q and~q,which violates the first condition about consistency.Consequently, thereisnoKratzerpremisesetthatsatisfiesalltheconditions(i)–(iv),whichcollapses Kratzer’s truth-conditions again to triviality.

    How damaging are these triviality results?In a certain sense,they seem to be quite harmless,for we can always have our base set not to include such tautologous propositions like T or q∨~q.The triviality results critically rely on there being these propositions to lump something that will contradict the antecedent,6In fact[4]has a third triviality case that invokes no tautologous propositions.However,the case is even much less damaging than the first two,for it requires the base set to include still more propositions that may look quite unnatural.and hence by having our base set to include no such propositions,we can be immune from the problem.But on the other hand,do we really have any positive reason to banish them from our base set?In her original paper,Kratzer only provides some very rough idea about what constraints we should impose on the base set:the propositions in the base set should be true in our world,humanly graspable,and persistent7A proposition is persistent just in case whenever it is true in a situation,it is also true in all larger situations that contain it as a part.For more discussions,see[5].([5],p. 634)(where these three constraints are not meant to be exhaustive).But this does not clearly rule out such propositions like T or q∨~q.So it may seem that Kratzer’s semantics is still not completely satisfactory.

    However,even in her original formulation,Kratzer already has some tools thatcansatisfactorilydealwiththeproblematiccasesraisedbyKanazawaetal.Theideais torecognisethatinasituationsemantics,tautologiescanbeambiguouswithrespectto theirlumpingcapacities.Forinstance,letT(asbefore)bethetautologousproposition that is true in all possible worlds but in no situations strictly smaller than a world; and let Tsbe the tautologous proposition that is true in all possible worlds and in all situations thereof.Then T and Tshave quite different lumping capacities:in any world w,T lumps every true proposition,whereas Tslumps only those true nonaccidental propositions,8Recall that a proposition is non-accidental if and only if it is true in all or none of the situations of a world.butislumpedbyeverytrueproposition.Logicaltautologies like Tsare very poor lumpers,and can be added to our premise sets without any problem(just as any other lawlike generalisations).But T is quite different;we have every reason to forbid adding it to our premise sets lest it lump all true propositions. Similarly,q∨~q,if interpreted as a non-accidental proposition that is true in all situations,can be added to our premise set without causing any problem;but if it is interpreted on an accidental reading as Kanazawa et al.take it to be,we have good reason to forbid adding it to our premise sets.So,this is how Kratzer replies to the triviality cases in a footnote to the revised version of the paper.

    …Since logical tautologies are non-accidental generalisation par excellence,Kanazawa et al.made a mistake by putting[T],rather than[Ts], in some of the critical premise sets they consider.[T]is an extremely strong lumper that will wreak havoc in any premise set for counterfactuals.That’s the kind of phenomenon that lumping semantics is all about [9,p.134 fn17].

    In a certain sense,Kratzer’s reply is just to dismiss those‘extremely strong lumpers’(e.g.,T or q∨~q interpreted accidentally)as highly dubious propositions to be banished from our consideration,for they will only‘wreak havoc in any premise setforcounterfactuals’.Whilstthiscouldbeasensiblewayofimprovingthelumping semantics,it also points to a very different approach to premise semantics in general. For if problematic propositions are to be ruled out anyway,we may also banish them in a much more direct manner than invoking the‘closure under lumping’requirement to constrain our premise sets.This leads Kratzer to think that she can have a better proposal,and she does develop such a new approach very soon in[8]and[7],as she reports later:

    I abandoned the approach of[5]as early as 1990 because I had found a better way of characterising the constraints for admissible premise sets. ([6],p.153)

    The main idea of[8]and[7]was to construct premise sets for counterfactuals in such a way that whenever they contain propositions p andq such that p lumps q,p also logically implies q.The requirement that premise sets be closed under lumping became superfluous,then.From the present perspective,the work reported in[5]was a useful intermediate step that eventually helped me find a way of getting rid of closure under lumping…The unpleasant results of[4]are all brought about by applying the closure conditions of[5]to premise sets containing propositions like singletons,tautologies,negations,and disjunctions.The new approach excluded the dangerous kinds of premises on general grounds, and at the same time eliminated the need for closure under lumping,too. ([6],p.154)

    On this new approach,premise sets are to be constructed from‘natural’propositions only.(Roughly,a proposition is natural if and only if it can be projected from a single actual situation s,in the sense that it should be true only in those situations that are maximally similar to some actual situation that contains s as a part.)In this way, we can directly rule out such problematic propositions like T,or accidental disjunctions like q∨~q,or accidental generalisations like(7d),etc.,by showing that they are not‘natural’propositions thus projectable from a single actual situation.As a result, we can drop the‘closure under lumping’condition altogether from our formulation of the semantics.In this sense,this new approach can provide an elegant formulation of premise semantics.

    Now,it is beyond the scope of the present paper to examine this new theory in more detail.But notice that this theory will demand a metaphysics of situations to help us pick up the right kind of‘natural’propositions to construct premise sets:We need situations in our ontology(in the sense that our ontology has to include some entities called‘possible worlds’and some entities called‘situations’that are parts of possible worlds);and we need situations to be properly structured by a part-whole relation and also by a resemblance relation.This is a metaphysical price we need to pay if we want to rule out problematic premises in this way.But it also makes us wonder whether this is a price worth paying.

    So here is my general worry for Kratzer’s premise semantics,which is a concern about its commitment to possible worlds and situations.For in a certain sense, premise semantics can be very attractive to philosophers mainly because it offers a viable alternative to the standard‘possible-worlds’semantics.It offers us,so to speak,a semantics for counterfactuals without possible worlds.To evaluate counterfactual conditionals on this semantics,all we need to do is consider what logically follows from the antecedent if we add suitable premises,rather than compare and arrange some putative entities called‘possible worlds’according to some murky notion of‘similarity’for worlds.Surely we still need to have some way to constrain the premises to be added,and the idea of having a‘lumping’structure amongst propositions remains to be a very natural proposal.But precisely at this point,Kratzer goesback to the resource of possible worlds,invoking situations(i.e.,parts of worlds)to help her formulate the required constraints.She tries to define lumping in terms of the mereological structures of situations by which to constrain the premise sets accordingly,and she even tries to get away with lumping and formulate the constraints directly in terms of features of situations.So in the end we still need to compare situations according to their similarities and mereological structures in order for this semantics to work.This may not be a problem if one already has good reason to accept an ontology of possible worlds and situations.But it does undermine a motivation for premise semantics that some may find attractive:i.e.,to have a viable alternative semantics for counterfactuals without possible worlds.

    This is not to say that a commitment to possible worlds and their associated metaphysics is so bad that we should try our best to avoid it.Some people may find Lewis’s semantics attractive precisely because its associated Humean metaphysics looks promising to them.Comparing possible worlds or parts of possible worlds according to their intrinsic similarities with regard to local arrangement of qualities may sound a very sensible way of doing semantics.One philosopher’s metaphysical burden can turn out to be another philosopher’s metaphysical benefit,and vice versa. But still,if we can have a semantics for counterfactuals without possible worlds,we can offer an alternative at least for those who are unhappy with possible worlds.

    In the next section,I will offer such an alternative semantics without appealing to possible worlds.The idea is to develop premise semantics along the‘lumping’approach that Kratzer originally proposes in[5],and to understand the lumping of propositions directly as a kind of grounding structure amongst propositions rather than in terms of the part-whole relationship of situations.I will argue that it can accommodate all the examples that motivate Kratzer’s semantics without committing us to an ontology of worlds or situations.It therefore offers a viable alternative,or so I claim.

    4 Premise Semantics Based on Grounding

    In this section,a premise semantics for counterfactuals based on grounding will be provided as a viable alternative.Here is an informal picture.A counterfactual conditionalistrueifandonlyifitsconsequentfollowslogicallyfromitsantecedentwhen weaddsomesuitablepremises.AsinKratzer’slumpingsemantics,wehavethesame constraints for suitable premises:(i)they should be true propositions;(ii)they should be compatible with the antecedent;and(iii)they should not lump any propositions that will contradict the antecedent.But instead of invoking an ontology of situations, we analyse lumping in terms of a grounding relation between propositions.Some propositions are grounded in other propositions.They are thus non-fundamental,in the sense that their beingtrueis something that canbeexplained furtherbysomethingelse:they are true in virtue of something else.So,if p is such a proposition that is grounded in other propositions,then adding p in our counterfactual reasoning should require us to add those propositions that are its grounds,such that p can remain true in the counterfactual scenario in virtue of these propositions.In this way,we can define lumping in terms of grounding:for any true propositions p and q,p lumps q if and only if p is grounded in q.

    Here I assume that grounding is a factive relation between propositions and is irreflexiveandasymmetric.Morespecifically,Itakeittobeabinaryrelationbetween propositionsinthesensethatitsbasiclogicalformis‘xisgroundediny’or‘y grounds x’,where‘x’and‘y’range over propositions or pluralities of propositions.(When p is grounded in a plurality of propositions one of which is q,we say that q is a partial ground of p,and that p is grounded partially in q.When p is grounded in q but not partially,wesaythatpisgrounded fullyinq.)Itakegroundingtobeafactiverelation in the sense that only true propositions can be grounded and can be the grounds.

    Philosophers are still debating about how to characterise the notion of grounding properly.9For example,see[2]and also other papers in[1].Some are more inclined to take grounding primarily as a relation between facts rather than between propositions.Some are inclined to allow grounding to be nonfactive.Some prefer taking grounding as a primitive relation,whilst some are trying to analyse it in other terms.All these are controversial issues,and I have no intentiontosettlethemhere.Forthepurposeofthispaper,however,Icanonlyassume that there is a sensible notion of grounding applying to true propositions.And if you are inclined to take grounding rather as a relation between facts or other fact-like entities,you can still define a derivative notion of‘grounding’that applies to true propositions.

    So,what are the propositions that are supposed to be grounded in other propositions,and what are their grounds?Since I take grounding to be a sort of explanatory relationship,I think it depends on what kind of explanation we have in mind.So, depending on the context,there can be a causal sense of grounding,a nomic sense of grounding,an epistemic sense of grounding,a metaphysical sense of grounding,and so on.But there are also paradigmatic cases of grounding:(i)an(accidental)disjunction is fully grounded in its true disjuncts(i.e.,p∨q is fully grounded in p,given that p is true);(ii)a conjunction is partially grounded in its conjuncts(i.e.,p∧q is partially grounded in p,given that p∧q is true);(iii)an(accidental)existential generalisation is fully grounded in its true instances(i.e.,(?x)φx is fully grounded in φa,given that φa is true);(iv)an(accidental)universal generalisation is partially grounded in its instances(i.e.,(?x)φx is partially grounded in φa,given that(?x)φx is true).

    With the notion of grounding in hand,we can now offer an official definition for lumping:

    Lumping(a grounding-based account)

    A proposition p lumps a proposition q(relative to a context)if and only if

    (i)p and q are true;and

    (ii)p is fully or partially grounded in q(according to the grounding relation as is understood in the context).

    ThisdefinitioncapturessomeofKratzer’sintuitions.Kratzerthinksthataproposition exemplifying a whole situation lumps those propositions exemplifying its parts.We canexplainthisintermsofgrounding.Forarguably,thewholeisgroundedinitsparts. Soapropositionexemplifyingthewholeisgroundedinthepropositionsexemplifying itsparts.Forinstance,supposingthatPaulapaintedastilllifebypaintingsomeapples and some bananas,then the proposition that Paula painted a still life is grounded partially in the proposition that Paula painted apples.Our definition therefore yields the desired result that the former lumps the latter.Hence,our definition agrees with Kratzer’s intuitions about lumping.

    Our definition also captures some of Goodman’s intuitions.Goodman thinks that if a proposition fails to be cotenable with the antecedent(in the sense that it could fail to be true if the antecedent were true),then it is unsuitable for being added in our counterfactual reasoning.We can explain this in terms of grounding as well.For arguably,failure of cotenability amounts to some sort of counterfactual dependence, which is a good indication of the obtaining of some grounding relation.So for instance,suppose that Boris did not come to the party but Olga did,but Olga wanted to avoid meeting Boris in such a way that she would not have been in the party if Boris had been there.In this case,the proposition that Olga was in the party fails to be cotenable with the counterfactual supposition that Boris came to the party.But the failure of cotenability also shows that Olga’s presence depends counterfactually upon Boris’s absence,which indicates that the proposition that Olga was in the party should be in some sense grounded in the proposition that Boris was absent from the party.According to our definition,then,the former lumps the latter,whilst the latter is incompatible with the counterfactual supposition that Boris came to the party.This explains why such a proposition is unsuitable for being added in our counterfactual reasoning.

    We can now offer our official truth-conditions for counterfactual conditionals.

    The Crucial Set and Premise Sets(a grounding-based version)

    Let F be a base set provided by the context,and p be a proposition. WedefineHF,p,calledthecrucialset,asthesetofallsubsetsAofF∪{p} satisfying the following conditions:

    (i)A is consistent

    (ii)p∈A

    (iii)A is closed under lumping;i.e.,for any q,r∈F,if q∈A and q is fully or partially grounded in r(according to the grounding relation as is understood in the context),then r∈A.

    Any such set A in HF,pis called a premise set.

    Premise semantics(a grounding-based version)

    Let F be a base set provided by the context.Then a counterfactual conditional p□→q is true(in this context)if and only if for every A∈HF,p,there is some B∈HF,psuch that A?B and B logically implies q.

    We now revisit the examples that motivates Kratzer’s semantics as discussed in the previous sections to see how our grounding-based semantics works.Let us examine the zebra case first.Recall that we are to evaluate the following counterfactual conditionals:

    (3)If a different animal had escaped instead,it would have been a zebra.

    (4)If a different animal had escaped instead,it might have been a gazelle.

    We wonder why the following propositions should not be included in our premise sets:

    (5) a.The animal that escaped was striped.

    b.The animal that escaped was black and white.

    c.The animal that escaped was a zebra.

    ……

    Our grounding-based account provides such an explanation.Suppose the zebra that actually escaped was named‘John’.Then it is reasonable to say that(5a)is true because John was the animal that escaped and John was striped.So we may say that (5a)is grounded(partially)in the proposition that John was the animal that escaped, and consequently no premise set should include(5a)on pain of inconsistency.For similar reasons,none of(5b),(5c),and so on,can be included in our premise sets,as each of them is also grounded(partially)in the proposition that John was the animal that escaped.As a result,our semantics can therefore correctly predict that(3)is false and(4)is true.

    Now,letusturntocasesinvolvingaccidentalandnon-accidentalgeneralisations. In the first case,our base set contains(at least)these relevant propositions:

    (7) a.Paula is in this room.

    b.Otto is in this room.

    c.Paula and Otto are the only persons in this room.

    d.All persons in this room are painters.

    e.Clara is not a painter.

    We are evaluating the following counterfactuals:

    (8)If Clara were also in this room,she would(still)not be a painter.

    (9)If Clara were also in this room,she might be a painter.

    Here the antecedent is this proposition:

    (10)Clara is in this room.

    We wonder why(7d)should not be included in our premise sets to make us predict (8)false and(9)true.Our grounding-based account provides an explanation.For arguably,all persons in this room are painters because Paula is in this room and is a painter,and Otto is in this room and is a painter,and Paula and Otto are the only persons in this room.So it is reasonable to say that(7d)is grounded(partially)in (7a),(7b),and(7c).But(7a),(7b),and(7c)form a set that is inconsistent with our antecedent(10).So our grounding-based account can explain why(7d)should not be included in any premise set.

    Now,consider the second case,which involves a non-accidental generalisation instead of an accidental generalisation.In this case,we are evaluating this counterfactual conditional:

    (11)If Eason were now in this room,he would be safe from freezing.

    Our base set contains(at least)these relevant propositions:

    (12) a.Paula is in this room.

    b.Otto is in this room.

    c.Paula and Otto are the only persons in this room.

    d.All persons in this room are safe from freezing.

    e.Eason is nearly frozen to death.

    We wonder why in this case,we should add(12d)to our premise sets to predict(11) true.Our grounding-based account also provides an explanation.For if we are to follow our reasoning in the previous case to banish(12d)from our premise sets,we will have to say that(12d)should be grounded in(12a),(12b),and(12c).But this makes the direction of explanation wrong.For unlike the previous case,it is implausible to say that all persons in this room are safe from freezing because Paula is in this room and safe from freezing,and Otto is in this room and safe from freezing,and Paula and Otto are the only persons in this room.On the contrary,we should rather say that Paulaissafefromfreezingbecauseallpersonsinthisroomaresafefromfreezingand Paula is in this room.Presumably,(12d)is intended to be a non-accidental or lawlike generalisation by reference to which we explain some other things,rather than an accidental generalisation which is to be explained by its confirming instances.So it is plausible to assume that(12d)is not grounded in any other propositions listed in (12).Our grounding-based account therefore explains why(12d)can be added to our premise sets without causing any problem.

    5 Conclusion

    The basic idea of premise semantics is intuitively plausible:A counterfactual conditional is true if and only if its consequent logically follows from its premises together with some suitable premises.But we still need to specify the constraints for what count as suitable premises to be added in our counterfactual reasoning.Goodman offers a‘cotenability’account to capture the constraints,but fails to characterise the very notion of cotenability independently of our intuitions about counterfactual conditionals.Kratzer offers a‘lumping’account to capture the constraints,but her theorycommitsustoametaphysicsofsituations.Inthispaper,Iproposeagroundingbasedaccounttocapturetheconstraint,whichcanavoidinvokingworldsorsituations on the one hand,and can be independent of our intuitions about counterfactuals on the other hand.My grounding-based version of premise semantics therefore provides a viable alternative semantics for counterfactual conditionals.

    [1] F.Correia and B.Schnieder(eds.),2012,Metaphysical Grounding:Understanding the Structure of Reality,Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

    [2] K.Fine,2012,“A guide to ground”,in F.Correia and B.Schnieder(eds.),Metaphysical Grounding:Understanding the Structure of Reality,Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

    [3] N.Goodman,1983,Fact,Fiction,andForecast,Cambridge,Mass:HarvardUniversity Press.

    [4] M.Kanazawa,S.Kaufmann and S.Peters,2005,“On the lumping semantics of counterfactuals”,Journal of Semantics,22(2),129–151.

    [5] A.Kratzer,1989,“An investigation of the lumps of thought”,Linguistics and Philosophy,12(5),607–653.

    [6] A.Kratzer,2005,“Constraining premise sets for counterfactuals”,Journal of Semantics,22(2),153–158.

    [7] A.Kratzer,2002,“Facts:Particulars or information units?”,Linguistics and Philosophy,25(5-6),655–670.

    [8] A.Kratzer,1990,“How specific is a fact?”,In Proceedings of the 1990 Conference on Theories of Partial Information,Center for Cognitive Science and College of Liberal Arts at the University of Texas at Austin.

    [9] A.Kratzer,2012,Modals and Conditionals,Oxford:Oxford University Press.

    [10] D.Lewis,1979,“Counterfactualdependenceandtime’sarrow”,No?s,13(4),455–476.

    聚合與立基:反事實(shí)條件句之前提語義學(xué)的辯護(hù)

    鄧敦民

    臺(tái)灣大學(xué) 哲學(xué)系

    dmdeng@ntu.edu.tw

    2016-12-20

    前提語義學(xué)的基本想法是主張反事實(shí)條件句宣稱我們可以從前件加上適當(dāng)?shù)那疤嵬茖?dǎo)出后件。Kratzer(1981,1989)發(fā)展了這樣的想法,引進(jìn)了前提集(premise sets)的概念,來表達(dá)我們加入前提的適當(dāng)方式,主張條件句p□→q為真,若且惟若每個(gè)前提集皆可被擴(kuò)張為邏輯上蘊(yùn)含后件的前提集。而Kratzer的計(jì)劃,便是要替前提集找到恰當(dāng)?shù)南拗?,可以使得反事?shí)條件句的真值條件正確。

    Kratzer(1989)使用了聚合(lumping)的概念來刻畫前提集的限制。這里的想法是,有些命題會(huì)聚合在一起,使得我們加入一個(gè)為前提,就會(huì)一起加入其余它所聚合的命題。而命題間的聚合關(guān)系,則是用情境語義學(xué)(situation semantics)中,在情境之間的部分與整體來定義。這樣的處理,可以解決Kratzer早期理論遇到的一些問題,但仍會(huì)遇到如Kanazawa等人(2005)所提出的困難。而Kratzer本人也很快的放棄了這條進(jìn)路,改而采用自然命題的概念來重構(gòu)其前提語義學(xué)。

    在本文中,我將辯護(hù)Kratzer(1989)的聚合語義學(xué)。我主張將聚合的概念,用立基(grounding)的概念來理解,以取代Kratzer所使用的情境概念。根據(jù)我的定義,命題p聚合命題q,意謂著p立基在q上,因此當(dāng)我們加入一個(gè)命題為前提時(shí),就會(huì)一起加入它所立基的命題。我主張的這種做法,可以成功處理聚合語義學(xué)的案例,并避開其困難。

    猜你喜歡
    條件句語義學(xué)命題
    條約演化解釋:合法性、語義學(xué)分析及近似概念
    法律方法(2021年3期)2021-03-16 05:57:16
    聚焦虛擬條件句的變式
    Hiddleston’s Causal Modeling Semantics and the Distinction between Forward-Tracking and Backtracking Counterfactuals*
    哈特的語義學(xué)
    下一站命題
    If條件句結(jié)構(gòu)的范疇認(rèn)知視角及翻譯策略
    文教資料(2016年3期)2016-03-16 20:12:26
    財(cái)產(chǎn)權(quán)概念的語義學(xué)考察
    2012年“春季擂臺(tái)”命題
    2011年“冬季擂臺(tái)”命題
    2011年“夏季擂臺(tái)”命題
    舔av片在线| 国产av不卡久久| 国产亚洲91精品色在线| av在线播放精品| 简卡轻食公司| 国产成人精品一,二区| 日韩国内少妇激情av| 亚洲精品乱码久久久久久按摩| 亚洲av福利一区| 插阴视频在线观看视频| 久久久精品大字幕| 国产av码专区亚洲av| 在线观看一区二区三区| 亚洲婷婷狠狠爱综合网| 免费黄网站久久成人精品| 搞女人的毛片| 亚洲自拍偷在线| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 91在线精品国自产拍蜜月| 成人av在线播放网站| 国产日韩欧美在线精品| 精品一区二区三区人妻视频| 精品午夜福利在线看| 亚洲va在线va天堂va国产| 久久久久久久久久久丰满| 伦理电影大哥的女人| 久久国产乱子免费精品| 久久韩国三级中文字幕| 天堂影院成人在线观看| 精品不卡国产一区二区三区| 久久久久久久久大av| 六月丁香七月| 日本一本二区三区精品| 日本黄大片高清| 97超视频在线观看视频| 欧美色视频一区免费| 国产成人精品一,二区| 日本-黄色视频高清免费观看| 亚洲av男天堂| 久久久色成人| 欧美变态另类bdsm刘玥| 国产午夜精品久久久久久一区二区三区| 成人特级av手机在线观看| 亚洲成人久久爱视频| 99久久精品一区二区三区| av在线蜜桃| 国产亚洲91精品色在线| 久久精品国产亚洲网站| av在线亚洲专区| 2021天堂中文幕一二区在线观| 国产亚洲最大av| 亚洲人与动物交配视频| 国产成人午夜福利电影在线观看| 少妇人妻一区二区三区视频| 久久6这里有精品| 久久精品国产99精品国产亚洲性色| 亚洲性久久影院| 村上凉子中文字幕在线| 免费大片18禁| 日本一二三区视频观看| 最近手机中文字幕大全| 搞女人的毛片| 国产白丝娇喘喷水9色精品| 最新中文字幕久久久久| 免费观看的影片在线观看| 亚洲在线观看片| 亚洲中文字幕一区二区三区有码在线看| 黑人高潮一二区| 毛片女人毛片| 日韩欧美在线乱码| 亚洲欧美日韩无卡精品| 天天躁日日操中文字幕| 尤物成人国产欧美一区二区三区| 麻豆久久精品国产亚洲av| 高清av免费在线| 成人性生交大片免费视频hd| 久久久久免费精品人妻一区二区| 在线观看一区二区三区| 男人和女人高潮做爰伦理| 国产免费又黄又爽又色| 汤姆久久久久久久影院中文字幕 | 黑人高潮一二区| 午夜精品在线福利| 欧美变态另类bdsm刘玥| 亚洲乱码一区二区免费版| 我要搜黄色片| 国产乱人偷精品视频| 欧美日韩一区二区视频在线观看视频在线 | 午夜激情福利司机影院| 国产午夜精品论理片| 亚洲精品日韩av片在线观看| 久久久久九九精品影院| 精品久久久久久久人妻蜜臀av| 亚洲精品乱码久久久久久按摩| 中国国产av一级| 免费看av在线观看网站| 欧美日韩综合久久久久久| 国产精品,欧美在线| 男插女下体视频免费在线播放| 亚洲在线观看片| 在线观看av片永久免费下载| 一个人免费在线观看电影| 国产精品蜜桃在线观看| 高清午夜精品一区二区三区| 成人特级av手机在线观看| 国产69精品久久久久777片| 熟妇人妻久久中文字幕3abv| 色综合亚洲欧美另类图片| 亚洲精品国产av成人精品| 啦啦啦观看免费观看视频高清| 午夜福利高清视频| 日本爱情动作片www.在线观看| 一卡2卡三卡四卡精品乱码亚洲| 亚洲经典国产精华液单| 精品午夜福利在线看| 亚洲成人久久爱视频| 日韩成人伦理影院| www.色视频.com| 毛片女人毛片| 国产免费男女视频| 亚洲精品色激情综合| 国产成人aa在线观看| 中国美白少妇内射xxxbb| 日本午夜av视频| 欧美成人a在线观看| 观看免费一级毛片| 亚洲欧美精品专区久久| 亚洲综合精品二区| 可以在线观看毛片的网站| 国产精品国产三级专区第一集| 搡老妇女老女人老熟妇| 亚洲在线自拍视频| 久久99精品国语久久久| 欧美成人a在线观看| 久久久精品大字幕| 欧美日韩精品成人综合77777| 欧美xxxx黑人xx丫x性爽| 国产成人a区在线观看| 日韩av不卡免费在线播放| 一个人免费在线观看电影| 色尼玛亚洲综合影院| 久久精品91蜜桃| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 久久精品国产99精品国产亚洲性色| 国产精品一区二区在线观看99 | 综合色丁香网| 99久久人妻综合| 三级国产精品欧美在线观看| 一区二区三区四区激情视频| 精品人妻一区二区三区麻豆| 久久99蜜桃精品久久| 丝袜美腿在线中文| 亚洲人成网站在线观看播放| 一个人观看的视频www高清免费观看| 尤物成人国产欧美一区二区三区| 日本五十路高清| 国产成人a∨麻豆精品| 真实男女啪啪啪动态图| av播播在线观看一区| 男女视频在线观看网站免费| 免费av观看视频| www日本黄色视频网| 最后的刺客免费高清国语| 国产精品野战在线观看| 日韩中字成人| 狂野欧美白嫩少妇大欣赏| 免费看光身美女| 国产精品久久久久久精品电影| 国产老妇伦熟女老妇高清| 国产午夜精品论理片| 亚洲伊人久久精品综合 | 国产精品1区2区在线观看.| 欧美成人a在线观看| 啦啦啦韩国在线观看视频| 亚洲欧美精品专区久久| 国产片特级美女逼逼视频| av在线亚洲专区| 国产成人91sexporn| 成人av在线播放网站| 日本熟妇午夜| 色哟哟·www| 91精品国产九色| 日本黄色视频三级网站网址| 成人午夜高清在线视频| 免费观看精品视频网站| 精品久久久久久久久亚洲| 国产精品嫩草影院av在线观看| 中文资源天堂在线| 欧美精品国产亚洲| 国产单亲对白刺激| 永久网站在线| 亚洲精品影视一区二区三区av| 成人一区二区视频在线观看| 精品一区二区免费观看| 国产单亲对白刺激| 国内少妇人妻偷人精品xxx网站| 成人午夜高清在线视频| 啦啦啦韩国在线观看视频| 婷婷色综合大香蕉| 亚洲aⅴ乱码一区二区在线播放| 亚洲精品456在线播放app| 精品久久久久久久人妻蜜臀av| 人体艺术视频欧美日本| 婷婷色麻豆天堂久久 | 欧美三级亚洲精品| 狠狠狠狠99中文字幕| 国产成人精品一,二区| 深夜a级毛片| 禁无遮挡网站| 国产精品1区2区在线观看.| 97在线视频观看| 欧美高清性xxxxhd video| 一区二区三区高清视频在线| 久久午夜福利片| 亚洲成av人片在线播放无| 99热网站在线观看| 特大巨黑吊av在线直播| ponron亚洲| 天天躁日日操中文字幕| 国产探花极品一区二区| 国产亚洲最大av| 午夜久久久久精精品| av在线观看视频网站免费| 亚洲精品国产av成人精品| 国产精品99久久久久久久久| 欧美一区二区国产精品久久精品| av黄色大香蕉| 26uuu在线亚洲综合色| 国产精品一区www在线观看| 看十八女毛片水多多多| 在线观看美女被高潮喷水网站| 久久久a久久爽久久v久久| 村上凉子中文字幕在线| 午夜激情欧美在线| 国产精品久久久久久久电影| 欧美成人a在线观看| 在线播放无遮挡| av免费在线看不卡| 蜜桃亚洲精品一区二区三区| 神马国产精品三级电影在线观看| 精品一区二区三区视频在线| 亚洲中文字幕日韩| 国产精品久久视频播放| 日本熟妇午夜| 久久久精品欧美日韩精品| 久久久a久久爽久久v久久| 日本色播在线视频| 久久精品国产亚洲网站| 天天躁夜夜躁狠狠久久av| 能在线免费看毛片的网站| 亚洲,欧美,日韩| 天堂√8在线中文| 中文字幕免费在线视频6| 国产乱人视频| 男插女下体视频免费在线播放| 亚洲最大成人中文| 免费观看人在逋| 联通29元200g的流量卡| 亚洲精品乱久久久久久| 久久精品国产鲁丝片午夜精品| 天天躁夜夜躁狠狠久久av| 日本免费a在线| www.色视频.com| 亚洲国产精品成人综合色| 国产一级毛片在线| 看十八女毛片水多多多| 欧美一区二区国产精品久久精品| 九九爱精品视频在线观看| 久久精品人妻少妇| 99国产精品一区二区蜜桃av| 国产在视频线在精品| 黄色日韩在线| 亚洲av成人精品一二三区| 亚洲欧美清纯卡通| av在线老鸭窝| 全区人妻精品视频| 我要看日韩黄色一级片| 国产成人精品一,二区| 男女啪啪激烈高潮av片| 又粗又硬又长又爽又黄的视频| 亚洲四区av| 国产又色又爽无遮挡免| 亚洲伊人久久精品综合 | 干丝袜人妻中文字幕| 三级男女做爰猛烈吃奶摸视频| 亚洲内射少妇av| 亚洲一区高清亚洲精品| 久久久久免费精品人妻一区二区| 91av网一区二区| 久久午夜福利片| 看片在线看免费视频| 亚洲真实伦在线观看| 国产一区二区在线av高清观看| 国产麻豆成人av免费视频| 久久鲁丝午夜福利片| 国产三级中文精品| 嫩草影院入口| 国产淫语在线视频| 色噜噜av男人的天堂激情| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区| 成人亚洲欧美一区二区av| 一级毛片久久久久久久久女| 久久久久久久久久久丰满| 人妻夜夜爽99麻豆av| 色播亚洲综合网| 国产 一区 欧美 日韩| 亚洲精华国产精华液的使用体验| 国产一区二区在线观看日韩| 久久久国产成人免费| 特级一级黄色大片| 一本—道久久a久久精品蜜桃钙片 精品乱码久久久久久99久播 | 国产人妻一区二区三区在| 国产伦理片在线播放av一区| 少妇丰满av| 午夜老司机福利剧场| 啦啦啦韩国在线观看视频| 村上凉子中文字幕在线| 美女内射精品一级片tv| 免费人成在线观看视频色| 精华霜和精华液先用哪个| 午夜福利视频1000在线观看| 少妇的逼水好多| 26uuu在线亚洲综合色| 亚洲最大成人手机在线| 中文资源天堂在线| 高清日韩中文字幕在线| 中文字幕精品亚洲无线码一区| 高清午夜精品一区二区三区| 乱人视频在线观看| 国产探花在线观看一区二区| 国产国拍精品亚洲av在线观看| 十八禁国产超污无遮挡网站| 国产精品,欧美在线| 又爽又黄a免费视频| 草草在线视频免费看| 一卡2卡三卡四卡精品乱码亚洲| 国产 一区精品| 久久精品国产亚洲网站| 亚洲av中文av极速乱| 在线免费十八禁| 天堂中文最新版在线下载 | 长腿黑丝高跟| 成人综合一区亚洲| 有码 亚洲区| 国产淫语在线视频| 一级毛片电影观看 | 国产欧美另类精品又又久久亚洲欧美| 久久久精品大字幕| 日本猛色少妇xxxxx猛交久久| 久久久a久久爽久久v久久| 中文欧美无线码| 青青草视频在线视频观看| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 成人鲁丝片一二三区免费| 欧美最新免费一区二区三区| 国产精品人妻久久久影院| 成年免费大片在线观看| 人体艺术视频欧美日本| 最近视频中文字幕2019在线8| 久久久久久久久久久丰满| 91午夜精品亚洲一区二区三区| 卡戴珊不雅视频在线播放| 青春草视频在线免费观看| 五月伊人婷婷丁香| av女优亚洲男人天堂| 亚洲最大成人中文| 亚洲欧洲日产国产| 亚洲不卡免费看| 日韩精品青青久久久久久| 天天躁日日操中文字幕| 国产午夜精品一二区理论片| 99久久中文字幕三级久久日本| 国产单亲对白刺激| 亚洲精品日韩av片在线观看| 国产精品久久电影中文字幕| 久久久久久久久大av| 老女人水多毛片| 美女黄网站色视频| 99热这里只有是精品50| 日本午夜av视频| 亚洲国产最新在线播放| 亚洲婷婷狠狠爱综合网| 高清视频免费观看一区二区 | 免费不卡的大黄色大毛片视频在线观看 | 视频中文字幕在线观看| 免费人成在线观看视频色| 99久久中文字幕三级久久日本| 欧美成人免费av一区二区三区| 在线观看av片永久免费下载| 18禁在线无遮挡免费观看视频| 欧美变态另类bdsm刘玥| 国内揄拍国产精品人妻在线| 亚洲人成网站在线播| 国产伦精品一区二区三区视频9| 久久精品国产鲁丝片午夜精品| 七月丁香在线播放| 99热精品在线国产| av在线天堂中文字幕| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜添av毛片| av视频在线观看入口| 国产黄片美女视频| 国内精品宾馆在线| 久久热精品热| 婷婷色av中文字幕| 亚洲欧洲国产日韩| 十八禁国产超污无遮挡网站| 国产亚洲午夜精品一区二区久久 | 国产成人精品一,二区| 五月玫瑰六月丁香| 中文字幕av在线有码专区| 成人漫画全彩无遮挡| 日韩国内少妇激情av| 毛片一级片免费看久久久久| 天堂中文最新版在线下载 | 久久久精品欧美日韩精品| 伦精品一区二区三区| 最近视频中文字幕2019在线8| 联通29元200g的流量卡| 黄片无遮挡物在线观看| 哪个播放器可以免费观看大片| 男插女下体视频免费在线播放| 国产黄片美女视频| 一级二级三级毛片免费看| 日韩视频在线欧美| 精品午夜福利在线看| 亚洲精品一区蜜桃| 免费播放大片免费观看视频在线观看 | 国产美女午夜福利| 亚洲精品aⅴ在线观看| 午夜免费激情av| 欧美人与善性xxx| 在线观看美女被高潮喷水网站| 中国美白少妇内射xxxbb| 精品午夜福利在线看| 精品久久久久久久久久久久久| 亚洲成人精品中文字幕电影| 国产黄片视频在线免费观看| 亚洲成av人片在线播放无| 成人特级av手机在线观看| 久久精品熟女亚洲av麻豆精品 | 汤姆久久久久久久影院中文字幕 | 国产一区有黄有色的免费视频 | 99国产精品一区二区蜜桃av| 精品久久久久久久久av| 国产精品一区二区性色av| 日韩高清综合在线| 欧美最新免费一区二区三区| 一夜夜www| 亚洲国产日韩欧美精品在线观看| 成年女人永久免费观看视频| 成人综合一区亚洲| 长腿黑丝高跟| 国产成人精品一,二区| 国产成年人精品一区二区| 久久久精品大字幕| 国产欧美另类精品又又久久亚洲欧美| 亚洲在线自拍视频| 亚洲av免费在线观看| 老师上课跳d突然被开到最大视频| 五月伊人婷婷丁香| 久久精品国产99精品国产亚洲性色| 亚洲精品乱码久久久久久按摩| 在现免费观看毛片| 1000部很黄的大片| 干丝袜人妻中文字幕| 99久久精品热视频| 99久久精品一区二区三区| 日本免费a在线| 在线观看66精品国产| 麻豆成人午夜福利视频| 少妇人妻一区二区三区视频| 在线播放国产精品三级| 麻豆国产97在线/欧美| 久久久久免费精品人妻一区二区| 午夜福利在线观看吧| 边亲边吃奶的免费视频| 超碰97精品在线观看| 久久久成人免费电影| 一级毛片aaaaaa免费看小| 免费看美女性在线毛片视频| av天堂中文字幕网| 水蜜桃什么品种好| 在线观看一区二区三区| 精品国内亚洲2022精品成人| 日本爱情动作片www.在线观看| 精品国产露脸久久av麻豆 | 好男人视频免费观看在线| 国产精品综合久久久久久久免费| 特大巨黑吊av在线直播| 爱豆传媒免费全集在线观看| av在线亚洲专区| 亚洲国产最新在线播放| 久久欧美精品欧美久久欧美| 内地一区二区视频在线| 成年女人永久免费观看视频| 欧美不卡视频在线免费观看| 亚洲欧美中文字幕日韩二区| 日本午夜av视频| 亚洲人成网站高清观看| 国产精品女同一区二区软件| 99视频精品全部免费 在线| 中文字幕精品亚洲无线码一区| 久久久久精品久久久久真实原创| 欧美97在线视频| 一个人免费在线观看电影| 你懂的网址亚洲精品在线观看 | 日韩制服骚丝袜av| 国产精品野战在线观看| 久久韩国三级中文字幕| 中文字幕av成人在线电影| 亚洲国产成人一精品久久久| 高清av免费在线| 国产精品乱码一区二三区的特点| 国产精品嫩草影院av在线观看| 国产精品福利在线免费观看| 丝袜喷水一区| 少妇裸体淫交视频免费看高清| 熟女电影av网| 免费看av在线观看网站| 国产精品人妻久久久影院| 久久久久久久久久成人| 日本欧美国产在线视频| 日本午夜av视频| 国产色婷婷99| 欧美激情在线99| 国产精品综合久久久久久久免费| 精品99又大又爽又粗少妇毛片| 国产成人福利小说| 国产白丝娇喘喷水9色精品| 乱系列少妇在线播放| 在线观看一区二区三区| 秋霞伦理黄片| 一个人观看的视频www高清免费观看| 欧美一区二区精品小视频在线| 如何舔出高潮| 国产精品三级大全| 看十八女毛片水多多多| 中文字幕精品亚洲无线码一区| 色综合亚洲欧美另类图片| 日韩在线高清观看一区二区三区| 一区二区三区四区激情视频| 伦理电影大哥的女人| 欧美激情在线99| 亚洲欧美日韩东京热| 最近中文字幕高清免费大全6| 成人高潮视频无遮挡免费网站| 噜噜噜噜噜久久久久久91| 啦啦啦观看免费观看视频高清| 亚洲精品国产成人久久av| 黄色日韩在线| 建设人人有责人人尽责人人享有的 | 日本黄色片子视频| 久久鲁丝午夜福利片| 国产精品久久久久久av不卡| 国产精品国产高清国产av| 天天躁夜夜躁狠狠久久av| 国产精品一区www在线观看| 黄片无遮挡物在线观看| 免费黄网站久久成人精品| 中文欧美无线码| 亚洲国产精品久久男人天堂| 亚洲av福利一区| 91精品一卡2卡3卡4卡| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜爱| 国产老妇女一区| 毛片女人毛片| 亚洲精品自拍成人| 麻豆av噜噜一区二区三区| 91av网一区二区| 直男gayav资源| 国产精品国产三级国产av玫瑰| 国产欧美日韩精品一区二区| 性插视频无遮挡在线免费观看| 国产极品天堂在线| 中文在线观看免费www的网站| 免费观看人在逋| 欧美精品一区二区大全| 亚洲精品一区蜜桃| 综合色丁香网| 久久久久久九九精品二区国产| 久久精品国产鲁丝片午夜精品| 久久综合国产亚洲精品| 成人毛片60女人毛片免费| 亚洲国产精品久久男人天堂| 成人漫画全彩无遮挡| 大话2 男鬼变身卡| 欧美成人午夜免费资源| 美女xxoo啪啪120秒动态图| 国产精品一区二区性色av| 欧美成人午夜免费资源| 欧美性猛交╳xxx乱大交人| 三级国产精品欧美在线观看| 亚洲国产精品久久男人天堂| 偷拍熟女少妇极品色| 大话2 男鬼变身卡| 色尼玛亚洲综合影院| 在线观看美女被高潮喷水网站| 欧美精品一区二区大全| 日韩欧美国产在线观看| 国产黄片视频在线免费观看| 久久精品人妻少妇| 日本一本二区三区精品| 一个人观看的视频www高清免费观看| av在线观看视频网站免费| 大又大粗又爽又黄少妇毛片口| 一区二区三区免费毛片| 91av网一区二区| 日韩欧美在线乱码| 精品欧美国产一区二区三| 久久99热这里只有精品18| 搞女人的毛片| 热99re8久久精品国产| 国产精品人妻久久久影院| 国产精品一区二区在线观看99 | 久久久国产成人免费|