• <tr id="yyy80"></tr>
  • <sup id="yyy80"></sup>
  • <tfoot id="yyy80"><noscript id="yyy80"></noscript></tfoot>
  • 99热精品在线国产_美女午夜性视频免费_国产精品国产高清国产av_av欧美777_自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇_亚洲熟女精品中文字幕_www日本黄色视频网_国产精品野战在线观看 ?

    New Wine in Old Bottles?
    ——Revisiting the Problem of Continuity and Discontinuity between Modern Chinese Intellectual History and the Confucian Tradition

    2011-02-18 10:42:22墨子刻ThomasMetzger
    中國思潮評論 2011年0期
    關(guān)鍵詞:墨子

    墨子刻(Thomas A.Metzger)

    I.The nature of Chinese modernity is a problem entailing the controversy about whether all modernizing nations are culturally and institutionally converging or are still diverging. Convergence implies discontinuity with premodern cultures, while divergence implies continuity with them.

    II.Since at least 1992, Chinese scholars have widely acceptedzhuan-xingshi-dai(an era of change from one type of society and culture to another type) as an accurate way to describe the current era in Chinese history. This term, however, logically implies that the discontinuities in China will be“more important”than the continuities. Yet whether or not they will be more important is still open to empirical investigation and to argument about what is“important”in the cultural-institutional structure of a society.

    III.Zhuan-xingalso logically implies other questions open to debate:

    1.Does history,normallyform systemically unified and logically coherent societal structures and then evolve from one structure to the next, or does it also normally take the form of a less systemic, eclectic mix of thoughts and behaviors? (To what extent does intellectual history take the form of systemically unified trends?)

    2.If history normally forms logically coherent societal structures, does it also include“global tides of events”(shi-jie-dechao-liu) irresistibly replacing an old societal structure with a new one, or is historical causation more complex and less deterministic, as the Max Weber’s sociological tradition holds?

    3.If there are such“tides,”then history itself implies a normative program answering the question“Where should China go?”(Zhong-guoxianghechuqu?) If, however, thee are no such“tides,”what is the epistemological basis for answering this question?

    IV.By complicating the question of historical causation, Weberian sociology also complicates the question of what is the“most important”aspect of society.

    1.One can say Weberian sociology describes a“society”by distinguishing not only between episodes, personalities, and patterns but also between nine patterns each of which can be described morphologically and quantitatively: 1.geography; 2.biological aspects of the population; 3.popular culture (i.e.paideia); 4.spatial distribution of population; 5.economy (technology, occupational structure, organization, patterns of production, distribution, and consumption); 6.stratification; 7.“thought”(si-xiang), i.e. propagated views of the more educated strata; 8.political life; 9.intersocietal relations.

    2.For almost every one of the nine patterns above there is a famous scholar claiming it is the causally decisive pattern in the development of societies. For instance, G. William Skinner has emphasized pattern #4 (spatial organization); Karl A. Wittfogel has emphasized pattern #8 (political life); pattern #9 (intersocietal relations) has been crucial for scholars studying how non-Western societies have developed in the last two centuries under the influence of the West; pattern #5 is widely regarded as causally decisive not only by Marxists but also by many non-Marxist social scientists like the major American sociologist Alex Inkeles. Pattern #3 (popular culture) has been much emphasized in research on Chinese modernization. Strikingly enough, however, a broad variety of Chinese and Western historians agree that in the case of China’s societal development in the twentieth century, a or the major causal role was played by pattern #7,“thought.”

    3.They also agree that as“thought”(si-xiang) changed in China beginning in the late nineteenth century, a major discontinuity occurred with the rise of a new vision of modernizing progress, according to which Chinese can progress by struggling dynamically to modernize, that is, to realize prosperity, national power, a society free of the ills of egoism (da-tong), and unsurpassed international prestige by both adopting modern science and technology and fully realizing the dignity, freedom, creativity, equality, and legal rights of all individuals, along with democracy.

    V.Controversy about the extent of the continuity between this vision of modernizing progress and the Confucian tradition:

    1.The May Fourth Movement and Weberian modernization theory have long agreed that this vision of modernizing progress is essentially discontinuous with the Confucian tradition and arose as a rational, nationalistic response to objective realities and self-evidently valid Western ideas, especially those making up modern science and technology.

    2.Since the 1970s, many arguments have emphasized the importance of continuities:

    a)Lü Shi-qiang: Liang Qi-chao etc. had deep Confucian beliefs;

    b)Wang Er-min and Liu Gui-sheng: Chinese origins, from 1860s on, of the idea of a cosmically-based“vast change in the world”:bian-ju,yun-hui,ying-shi-zhi-bian,Gong-yangzhuan, optimism;

    c)Confucian values were used to form image of Western values:tuo-gugai-zhi,XixueyuanchuZhong-guo, Xu Fu-guan’s vision of democracy, which about coincided with Yin Hai-guang’s;

    d)Later research;

    e)If the modernization movement in China arose mainly out of a rational, nationalistic response to the realities and ideas introduced by the West (Benjamin I. Schwartz), why did this movement develop in a dynamic, utopian way so different from the ways in which other non-Western societies reacted to essentially the same realities and ideas (Rhoads Murphey)?

    f)Chinese adopting Western values were not just passive, credulous students of Western thought. Since at least Liang Qi-chao, Chinese intellectuals have seen themselves as judges and critics of Western thought, using their own criteria to select some Western ideas and reject others (qu-she). For instance, with few if any exceptions, they rejected the GMWER (bu-ke-zhi-lun), Burkean conservatism, and (at least until recently) the outlook most central to the West’sjing-shenchuan-tong(cultural-spiritual tradition), namely, Christianity. One has to consider the relation between the Confucian tradition and the criteria Chinese used in evaluating Western ideas. Zheng Jia-dong on Mu Zong-san’s evaluation of Kant’s ideas. Even more basically, one can ask why in China fundamentalism and total rejection of foreign values was restricted to scholars like Wo-ren and did not become a mainstream, as it did in the Muslim world. Was there any relation between the Confucian tradition and the radical cultural self-criticism that quickly became central to the modern Chinese intellectual mainstream?

    3.Even if the continuities were important, the importance of the discontinuities also is a major question, the answer to which can be deepened when the continuities are carefully considered. In his 1999 book, Gao Rui-quan offered a new argument about the importance of the discontinuities: they amounted to the formation of a new“tradition”.

    VI.Philosophical and methodological arguments affecting the analysis of continuity and discontinuity in the history of thought.

    1.Normative or factual continuity and discontinuity?

    2.The“l(fā)inguistic turn”:“thought”is“l(fā)inguistic practice,”or, at the very least, the verbal form of thought is extremely important and is the aspect of thought most susceptible to empirical description avoiding prejudgment and personal bias.

    3.Words versus the meanings of words: the importance of context.

    4.“Doctrine”(xue-shuo) versus“train of thought”(si-lu) versus“discourse”(hua-yu).

    5.Discourse: shared premises, shared agenda, and idiosyncratic, controversial arguments.

    6.Discourses as“free-floating symbolic resources”(S.N. Eisenstadt). Shared premises and idiosyncratic arguments are inseparable; idiosyncratic arguments can partly or wholly reject shared premises; but often premises are widely and persistently shared by texts otherwise disagreeing with each other.

    7.To find premises: etic disaggregation and etic recombination of the connotations of a word, as illustrated by Huang Ke-wu’s analysis of the meaning of“freedom”for Yan Fu.

    8.Why are culturally inherited premises important? The GMWER; the shift from rationalism to historicism, and then to neo-Hegelianism (Charles Taylor); the resulting shift from“reason”to tension between ROST (local, ephemeral historical-cultural-linguistic rules of successful thinking) and CR (critical reflexivity oriented to universal truth and objective reality); the distinction between“observation sentences”and the interpretation of theLebenswelt.

    9.ROST about what? Goals, means to reach them, other aspects of the given world, and the nature of knowledge.

    10.The distinction between epistemological optimism and epistemological pessimism is a neo-Hegelian one, not a rationalistic one.

    11.“Morally critical consciousness”(pi-panyi-shi): how choose between ROST (qu-she) if“reason”is unavailable? The philosophical issues. How tenable is GMWER?

    VII.The discourse #1 thesis: four tradition-rooted premises common to all the leading modern Chinese intellectual trends (Chinese Marxism, Chinese liberalism, modern Confucian humanism, and Sunism), namely epistemological optimism, the utopian goal of a world free of the ills of egoism, belief in a cosmic-historical force supporting the efforts of the moral hero, and belief in an antimony in the given nature of human beings.

    VIII.Premise #1: epistemological optimism.

    1.Continuing rationalism, if not rationalistic metaphysics, as faith in the objective, universally identical meaning of“reason”and“morality.”Rejection of the GMWER idea that reasoning varies to a large extent depending on ROST.

    2.Supplementing deduction and induction, e.g. with“dialectical reasoning”or a major emphasis on“on the basis of many data and considerations, summing up the nature of a massive, monolithic whole”(zong-jie-chu-lai-de), instead of being cautious in going beyond“observation sentences.”Frombian-jutoshi-jie-dechao-liu,tong-yi-deshi-jieli-shijin-cheng, andjiushi-jie-deshi-ming-gan. From“backwardness”to“transcending the West”: turning the perception of historical facts into a“springboard”(tiao-yue-shi-detan-xing-ban) for hopeful action in the future.

    3.Epistemological optimism and the Neo-Confucian“sense of predicament.”The latter was an aspect of premise #4 below, i.e. the combination of the optimistic idea that the human mind has the ability to“know the True Way”(zhi-dao) with the pessimistic idea that it is currently subject to radical moral and intellectual weakness preventing successful exercise of this ability. Confucian epistemological optimism refers to how this pessimistic sense of intellectual and moral weakness remained tied to the optimistic idea above, instead of turning into the GMWER’s pessimistic critique of the scope of knowledge. Human nature in the present time and place versus human nature throughout history. Chinese moral and epistemological pessimism applies to the former, Western, to the latter. Is the moral-intellectual quality of peoplehereandnowbasically different from what it was or will be?

    4.Confucian epistemological optimism distinguished from“dogmatism”(du-duan-lun) and authoritarianism. From the neo-Hegelian standpoint, no intellectual tradition can avoid all dogmatism. The question is the extent to which ROST encourage doubt and free disputation.

    IX.Premise #2: the goal of a humanity without the ills of egoism.

    1.Da-tong, etc. Ada-gongwu-siworld withoutli-jizhu-yi,ji-de-li-yi-zhe,bo-xue,ge-he,fen-yun, etc. Utilitarianism asjiyulierliren.

    2.Was“equality”the main point of emphasis in the modern Chinese vision ofda-tong? The centrality of the egoism problem is clear from a comparison of the whole spectrum of modern Chinese political philosophy with that of Western liberalism. Making use of Ferdinand Toennies’ distinction, we can say the former put primacy on the goal ofGemeinschaft(she-qushe-hui), the latter, on that ofGesellschaft(jie-sheshe-huiorge-renshe-hui).

    a)Gesellschaftis based on epistemological pessimism, moral pessimism, and ontological individualism, or even the idea of ego as ontologically superior to the individual as alter, as indicated by Jin Yue-lin’s point that the GMWER is based onwei-zhufang-shi, i.e. any ontological proposition about anything except the individual as ego (zhu-ti) is open to doubt.Gemeinschaftis based on epistemological optimism, including belief in the knowability of objective norms, on moral optimism, and on the ontological equality of the individual, the group, and indeed all things (as Wang Yang-ming said,daojishi,shijidao, and Professor Gao speaks of “a this-worldly sense of what ultimately matters”[ru-shizhong-jiguan-huai]).

    b)InGesellschaft, the combination of epistemological pessimism, moral pessimism, and the ontological superiority of the individual as ego puts primacy on the horizontal interactions of free, equal, and egoistic individuals in the intellectual, economic, and political marketplaces, not on the vertical flow of authority exercised by an elite afflicted by egoism and unable to grasp norms based on knowledge; harmony ultimately depends on an“invisible hand.”InGemeinschaft, the combination of epistemological optimism, moral optimism, and the ontological equality of individual and group interests puts primacy on the vertical authority exercised by a morally and intellectually enlightened vanguard (xian-zhixian-jue)transcending egoism and thus able to act as“the conscience of society”(she-hui-deliang-xin), resolving the conflicts between egoistic individuals in the three marketplaces. In other words, as Yan Fu indicated,Gemeinschafttakes theschoolled by enlightened teachers as the paradigm of the free society,Gesellschaftuses themarketplaceas such a paradigm.

    c)While Hume said“ought”cannot be inferred from“is,”this contrast betweenGemeinschaftandGesellschaftindicates that the morally legitimate balance between horizontal and vertical organization is logically implied by epistemological beliefs.

    d)The modernda-tongideal refers to theGemeinschaftparadigm. Modern Chinese intellectuals and Western liberals equally use worlds like“the dignity of the individual,”“the liberation of the individual,”“equality,”“democracy,”“l(fā)aw,”and“human rights”and believe these words have the same meaning east and west, but the meanings of these in aGemeinschaftcontext differ from their meanings in aGesellschaftcontext. (Hence the clash between discourses #1 and #2.)

    e)Emphasizing how deeply and widely Chinese during the first half of the twentieth century came to believe in the goal of realizing“the Great Oneness,”Professor Gao ascribes this trend to various problems that arose in the twentieth century and caused people to“pursue a new social ideal.”To be sure, this being a time of national crisis,“value disorientation,”and increasing disillusionment with Western civilization, it was natural for people to turn to radicalness and hope to build a society free of the inequalities afflicting the West. It was no accident, however, that the“new social ideal”they came to believe in was that of theGemeinschaftso strongly idealized by the Confucian tradition. The paradigm they so fervently believed in was not a new idea discontinuous with their traditional heritage.

    3.Professor Gao rightly says that the modern Chineseda-tongconcept was inseparable from the“idea of progress,”but I disagree with his emphasis on the discontinuity between this modern Chinese idea of progress and the Confucian tradition.

    a)Distinguishing between continuity with premodern Chinese behavior and with mainstream Confucian ideas.

    b)Confucian roots of the modern Chinese emphasis on material prosperity, on utilitarianism, and on ideas like freedom, equality, democracy.

    c)Did the Confucian tradition include any idea of progress as future, creative, continuous improvements realizing a morally and materially ideal world basically different from the current world of selfishness and material suffering? The“theory of the dynastic cycle”(xun-huan-lun) versus the Gong-yang vision and Zhang Zai’s vision of a“perfect peace”(tai-ping) lasting for“ten thousand generations.”Thefu-guproblem: given that all norms refer to future actions, what is more important, believing that the morally perfect segment of history is in the past rather than in the future, or believing that history includes a morally deficient present? Intensifying the moral imperative by not only believing that complete implementation is completely practicable and that it has in fact been accomplished (the negation of utopianism), but also believing that purely spiritual implementation is insufficient, that there also must be full material implementation in“this world”(ru-shi-dezhong-jiguan-huai). Scholars emphasizing the Confucian, Buddhist, and Daoist aspects of the modern Chinese quest for“meaning”have neglected this uniquely materialistic aspect of Confucian spirituality. The problem ofsu-ming-lun(fatalism): thetian-mingandqi-bingissue. Zhu Xi’s condemnation of fatalism and his emphasis onming-zhi-zheng(one’s true fate). The problem of a clear contrast between ideal and reality (you-daoandwu-dao), of“axial”civilizations, and of Weberian“tension”between ideal and reality. The manifestation of Weber’s“tension”in bureaucratic behavior during the Qing dynasty and in the many institutional transformations during the last millennia. The limited value of macroscopic, theoretical comparisons claiming that the tension between ideal and reality was“l(fā)ess”in premodern China than in the premodern West (whether it was less or more is a question different from whether it was the source of modern Chinese dynamism and whether less is better or worse than more).

    X.Premise #3: a cosmic-historical force supporting the efforts of the moral hero.

    1.In Confucian as well as modern Chinese thought, history was a struggle between moral efforts in the present and bad tendencies opposed to these efforts (see XI below). These efforts, however, were conceived of as inseparable from a cosmic-historical force supporting them; from the goal of a world without the ills of egoism, making these efforts meaningful; and from epistemological optimism, according to which the objective nature of this struggle was fully knowable. Thus, contrary to Schwartz, in conceptualizing the relation between their future efforts and a cosmic-historical evolution in accord with these efforts, modern Chinese intellectuals did not just borrow ideas from European thought. Indeed, the emerging idea that Chinese would have to“save the world,”not just“save China”(in Sun Yat-sen’s terms,jiuZhong-guo,jiushi-jie) was contrary to all European ideas on the subject.

    2.In conceptualizing this supporting cosmic-historical force, Chinese reacted to the realities and ideas introduced by the West by redescribing this force and the nature of the heroic efforts needed to supplement it. They put into the background the Neo-Confucian idea of“Heaven”(tian) as a cosmic force the omnipotent and totally benign“outer”expression of which would be caused by the“inner,”spiritual efforts of the sage, as Zhu Xi explicitly said. Instead, talking of“history,”“society,”and“culture,”they habitually referred to an“outer,”“global tide of events”(shi-jie-dechao-liu) ensuring the success of“outer”activities carried out by properly oriented citizens, whether“movements”(yun-dong), a revolution, governmental policies, education, or some combination of these. Hence that redefinition of the moral hero first noted by Chang Hao in his 1971 book and richly documented by Gu Hong-liang in his 2005 book: having been a sage, he or she became a regular citizen.

    XI.Premise #4: an antimony (er-lübei-fan) in the given nature of human beings.

    1.Both Neo-Confucianism and modern Chinese thought conceptualized the needed linkage between human efforts and the supporting cosmic-historical force as currently unrealized and impeded by“inner”and“outer”tendencies preventing this linkage. Such was the“predicament”I have tried to describe. In the Neo-Confucian case, this predicament centered on the difficulty of“l(fā)inking together”(guan-tong) the“human mind”(ren-xin), the ultimate“principles”of the cosmos (li), and“material things and happenings”(wu). In the modern context, these difficulies centered on figuring out how outer material process and the intentions of the moral hero formed a seamless continuum. Mao’s materialism and Tang Jun-yi’s idealism both were attempts to figure out how to form this seamless continuum. Conceptualizing it was necessary to achieve the seamless oneness of aGemeinschaftfree of “painful fissures disrupting human harmony”(ge-he,lie-hen).

    2.The ultimate source of these tendencies currently blocking realization of the idealGemeinschaftwas to some extent cosmic, but most importantly it was the antimony or contradiction in the given nature of human beings. On the one hand, human beings were completely capable of creating a world free of the ills of egoism, whether by achieving sagehood or creating a“new culture,”a“new China,”an“ideal China,”a“new people,”or a“new kind of human being”(xin-ren) (Wang Fan-sen) without these ills. On the other hand, human beings at home and abroad repeatedly fell into egotism and intellectual confusion, whether inflicting imperialism on China or misbehaving in the domestic arena.

    3.Until the 1970s, neither Western or Chinese students of Chinese thought were interested in describing this antimony central to Chinese thought because they studied Chinese thought mostly in a normative or philosophical way, as illustrated by the New Confucians’ interest in showing that the Confucian understanding of “experience”was more accurate than Kant’s, or by Wm. Theodore de Bary’s interest in revealing the“individualistic”and“l(fā)iberal”aspects of the Confucian tradition.

    4.The Weberian“tension”discussed above, I think, would not have been possible without this perception of an antimony at the center of human nature. Because of this antimony, Confucians felt morally compelled to pursue their utopian goal; perceived themselves as perpetually failing to reach it; and were perpetually unable to stop trying to reach it. The cultural pervasiveness of this tension can be seen in the Confucian division of history into an era when the human ability to create an ideal world was successfully exercised and an era when it was not. This tension is comparable to the one Weber saw as the cause for the capitalistic restructuring of European society from the sixteenth century on. I see the Chinese version of it as the main cause for China’s distinctively dynamic and utopian response to the realities and ideas injected into the Chinese scene by the West in the late nineteenth century. With this tension, Chinese interpreted these realities and ideas by turning history into a springboard (tiao-yue-shi-detan-xing-ban) from which they could leap out of an era of moral failure into one of moral success and so could re-enter the center of the global community, thus becoming able to“save the world”(jiushi-jie).

    XII.The importance of the four tradition-rooted premises.

    1.Historical importance. Needed to grasp intellectual change in China during the last two centuries, i.e. the mix of continuities and discontinuities; but not all modern Chinese thought shared all four premises.

    2.Needed to develop the typology of societies by going beyond schemes like modern-premodern-postmodern or democratic versus dictatorial, and by looking further into the divergence problem in modernization theory. I believe the evidence is strong that Chinese modernity will diverge from Western liberal modernity in leaning toward aGemeinschaftmodel strongly rejected in the West.

    3.Needed to alleviate international tensions by replacing mutual denunciations with an increase in mutual understanding: this is not a fight between freedom and oppression but one between profoundly different conceptions of freedom.

    4.Needed to develop political philosophy. If political philosophers aim to improve the public discussion of political life, how can they improve it without first describing it, and how can they describe it without describing culturally-inherited premises basic to it? Moreover, instead of simply assuming that Western liberalism is the world’s leading political philosophy, Chinese and Western philosophers can debate the pros and cons of the current Western liberal paradigm (that primacy of horizontal interactions logically required by the mix of epistemological pessimism, moral pessimism, and the ontological primacy of the individual as ego) and the current Chinese mainstream paradigm (that primacy of vertical interactions logically required by the mix of epistemological optimism, moral optimism, and the ontological equality of the individual, the group, and all other things and happenings). Using Tang Jun-yi’s categorization of the topics of philosophy, one can reopen the question of the relation between ontological-epistemological knowledge and moral-political norms.

    XIII.Problems in Modern Scholarship East and West Impeding the Uncovering and Description of Culturally Inherited Premises

    1.Continuing reluctance to accept Weber’s advice maximally to separate description from evaluation. For instance, one can recognize as a fact that a) values inherited from the Confucian tradition persisted in the twentieth century and helped Chinese modernize and also believe b) that these Confucian values impede optimal modernization. But scholars recognizing a) sometimes fear that emphasizing a) will weaken their argument against the New Confucian insistence that optimal modernization depends on full acceptance of the core Confucian values.

    2.The“axial”ethos of the“ivory tower.”This concerns the relation between the“ivory tower”and the marble citadel (xiang-ya-taandda-li-shi-decheng-bao). According to the ethos created by what Karl Jaspers and S. N. Eisenstadt call the rise of“axial”civilizations, the ivory tower arose east and west as“intellectuals”took on the moral mission to alleviate humankind’s misery by denouncing the failure of“the marble citadel”(i.e. the ruler, the political center) to act in accord with high moral ideals. Such was what Xu Fu-guan called the ivory tower’syou-huanyi-shi(sense of concern about the disasters in the world), their“spirit of protest”(kang-yijing-shen). Such is the historical source of the modern Chinese belief that intellectuals can and must serve as“the conscience of society”(she-hui-deliang-xin), along with Xu Fu-guan’s demand that they never praise the marble citadel, only criticize it. In modern times, however, it has become clear that the beliefs formed by the ivory tower also can contribute to the world’s disasters: disasters can be caused by the influence of culturally-inherited premises; these can be discovered and criticized only in the ivory tower; and the ivory tower has usually failed to uncover them. It probably wants to avoid uncovering them by limiting criticism of itself. It is quite willing to criticize specific doctrines produced by the ivory tower, such as materialism or idealism, but it is not willing to allow criticism undermining its deepest belief, namely, that the main source of the world’s troubles is the marble citadel, not the ivory tower. If the ivory tower looked deeply into culturally inherited premises, it might find itself as guilty as the marble citadel of causing the world’s great disasters and might thus undermine its traditional sense of identity and moral superiority. Yet it may be necessary to redefine the ethos of the intellectual if the world is moving, as Mu Zong-san said, from an era of“subordination”(li-shu) to one of“coordination”(dui-lie).

    3.The task of uncovering culturally inherited premises cannot seem worthwhile unless one agrees with the GMWER’s criticism of rationalism, accepts neo-Hegelianism, and also accepts the methodological points above about how to describe discourses. But the GMWER is the usual mix of insights and misunderstanding.

    XIV.Bibliographical note. The documentation and the arguments pertaining to these four premises are various and entail a disagreement with Professor Chang Hao. To begin with,EscapefromPredicament(N.Y.: Columbia University Press, 1977) emphasized premise #2 along with its corollary of“l(fā)inkage,”the distinctive, prevalent Chinese goal, shared by Neo-Confucianism with major modern trends like Maoism, of not only conceptualizing the seamless oneness of self, group, and cosmos but also realizing this oneness by turning concrete, contemporary historical reality into an aspect of it.

    This book also emphasized premise #4, the Neo-Confucian concept of the self as caught in a“predicament”due to the tension or antinomy between its“transnatural”power to realize“l(fā)inkage”and its persistent tendency toward intellectual confusion and the moral weakness of egoism (e.g. ibid., pp. 119, 121, 123, 134, 158).

    Premise #3 was described most clearly in my“Selfhood and Authority in Neo-Confucian Political Culture,”in Arthur Kleinman and Tsung-yi Lin, eds.,NormalandAbnormalBehaviorinChineseCulture(Dordrecht, Boston, London: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1981), pp. 7-27, which analyzed“nine assumptions defining the interaction between moral hero and cosmic-historical process [that] have been common to so much thought not only in premodern times but also after thought became ‘secularized’ in China. Secularization meant that the traditional, organismic and religious view of ‘Man’ as directly oriented to the universals of ‘Heaven and Earth’ was replaced by the modern vocabulary of ‘history’, ‘society’, and ‘culture’, which all evolved in ‘stages’”(ibid., p. 16).

    An earlier version of this analysis is in my“T’ang Chün-i and the Conditions of Transformative Thinking in Contemporary China,”which was presented as a paper at Columbia University in 1977, undoubtedly shared with Professor Chang, and published inTheAmericanAsianReview3:1 (spring 1985), pp. 1-47. This version emphasized that the modern rise of a“secular vocabulary”(ibid,. p. 31) had not interrupted the continuities between Tang’s “transformative”modern Chinese thought and Neo-Confucianism with regard to“l(fā)inkage”and the concept of the“moral hero”(ibid., pp. 21-22, 37-38, 43); that in Tang’s transformative thought, the“cosmos”included not only“the mind of Heaven”(tian-xin) as its ultimate principle but also a“cosmic-historical process”in the form of a“morally transformative force”filled with“power”and creating a global“tide of events”(chao-liu) (ibid., pp. 23, 30, 43); and that what Tang“shared with....other transformative thinkers”such as Mao was“the perception of the gap between the intentions of the moral hero and the transformative tendency in history, and the idea that closing this gap at least partly depended on figuring out how outer material processes and the feelings of the moral hero formed a single continuum”(ibid., pp. 28, 23). This viewpoint was also expressed in my“Author’s Reply,”part of a review symposium onEscapefromPredicamentinTheJournalofAsianStudies39:2 (February 1980), pp. 237-290. See ibid., pp. 286-287. (Hereafter“review symposium.”)

    As for premise #1, I first focused on it in“Some Ancient Roots of Modern Chinese Thought: This-worldliness, Epistemological Optimism, Doctrinality, and the Emergence of Reflexivity in the Eastern Chou,”inEarlyChina, vols. 11-12 (1985-1987), pp. 61-117, a text based on a paper I presented in 1985 at a conference on reflexivity organized by S.N. Eisenstadt. Arousing considerable skepticism, including that of Professors Eisenstadt and Benjamin I. Schwartz, it documented the idea of a contrast between the epistemological optimism of the Chinese intellectual mainstream, modern and premodern, and the epistemological pessimism basic to the modern liberal West. In myACloudAcrossthePacific:EssaysontheClashbetweenChineseandWesternPoliticalTheoriesToday(Hong Kong: The Chinese University Press, 2005), I further documented the themes above by describing China’s modern“discourse #1”as based on the four Chinese tradition-rooted premises above and contrasting it with the modern liberal West’s“discourse #2,”which emerged out of the Great Modern Western Epistemological Revolution (GMWER) going back to the seventeenth century.

    This book used a neo-Hegelian concept of“discourse”emphasizing how all human thought, or at least all public moral-political discussion, is made up of a) local, ephemeral historical-cultural-linguistic“rules of successful thinking”(ROST) or premises virtually indisputable in the eyes of the we-group using them; and b) a critical reflexivity oriented to universal truth and objective reality (CR). Thus a discourse combines shared premises blurred in together with idiosyncratic, controversial arguments, not simply as some shared“value system”the content of which can be briefly summed up as a list of fixed beliefs. Values are living thoughts inherently forming out of controversy, not only shared beliefs. Professor Stephen C. Angle calls this approach a“monolithic”one to distinguish it from his, which tends to avoid the problem of shared premises, but I would argue that the empirically most accurate way to understand what historical actors believed is to try to catch this intersection of shared premises with idiosyncratic trains of thought. Moreover, Angle seems to be wrong in holding that my“monolithic approach”“makes it relatively difficult to talk about, or even to recognize, differences among thinkers who participate in a single discourse.”Such differences are at the very center ofACloudAcrossthePacific. SeeChinaReviewInternational14:1 (spring 2007), pp. 28-29.

    Today, this concept of discourse has been little applied, whether by philosophers, historians, or social scientists. A good deal of scholarship, however, has come to emphasize factual continuities between the Confucian tradition and not only aspects of contemporary Chinese life often regarded as impeding modernization, such as authoritarianism and particularism, but also aspects integral to the leading Chinese efforts to modernize. The latter include not only traditional aspects of the popular culture, like the emphasis on family solidarity, frugality, and education, but also premises (ROST) used by Chinese to conceptualize modern life; seeACloudAcrossthePacific, pp. 154-157, and my“Continuities and Discontinuities between Modern and Premodern China: Some Neglected Methodological and Substantive Issues,”in Paul A. Cohen, Merle Goldman, eds.,IdeasAcrossCultures:EssaysonChineseThoughtinHonorofBenjaminI.Schwartz(Cambridge, MA: Council on East Asian Studies, Harvard University, 1990), p. 283.

    Great light on these intellectual continuities has been shed by the publications of Max Ko-wu Huang, such as his“Hu Shi yu He-xu-li (Hu Shi and Huxley),”inJin-dai-shiyan-jiu-suoji-kan, vol. 60 (June 2008), pp. 43-83; his books on Yan Fu and Liang Qi-chao; his“Cong zhui-qiu zheng-dao dao ren-tong guo-zu: Qing-mo Zhong-guo gong-si guan-nian-de chong-zheng (From Seeking the True Way to Identifying with the Nation: Reformulating the Distinction between Public and Private in China during Late Qing Times),”in Huang Ko-wu, Chang Che-chia, eds.,Gongyusi:Jin-daiZhong-guoge-tiyuzheng-ti-zhichong-jian(Public and Private: The Reconstruction of the Self and the Whole in Modern China; Taipei: Institute of Modern History, Academia Sinica, 2000), pp. 59-112, reprinted in Xu Ji-lin, ed.,Gong-gong-xingyugong-min-guan(The Concepts of the Public and of Citizenship: Shanghai: Jiang-su ren-min chu-ban-she, 2006), pp. 40-79; and his“Qing-mo Min-chu-de min-zhu si-xiang: yi-yi yu yuan-yuan (The Concept of Democracy in China during late Qing and Early Republican Years: Its Meaning and Origins),”in Zhong-yang yan-jiu-yuan, Jin-dai-shi yan-jiu-suo, ed.,Zhong-guoxian-dai-hualun-wen-ji(Symposium on Modernization in China, 1860-1949; Nangang: Zhong-yang yan-jiu-yuan, Jin-dai-shi yan-jiu-suo, 1991), pp. 363-398.

    Wang Er-min, Wang Fan-sen, and Liu Gui-sheng have brilliantly contributed to the understanding of these continuities, and agreement with the above thesis of the four premises is evident in the writings of Professor Chang Hao. His own publications do not discuss premise #1 (epistemological optimism), but in the letter quoted on the book jacket ofACloudAcrossthePacific, Chang referred to my“trailblazing discovery of a crucial aspect of modern Chinese thought, what [Metzger] calls epistemological optimism,”and in his letter recommending publication of this book, he did not question its emphasis on the traditional roots of epistemological optimism. Chang also does not directly focus on premise #2 (an ideal world free of the ills of egoism), but no China scholar known to me disputes the modern prevalence and traditional roots of this ideal (although Professor Gao Ruiquan perhaps sees it as an“old bottle filled with new wine”).

    Chang’s acceptance of premise #4 is apparent from Wang Fan-sen’s description as an original view of Chang’s the proposition that“Confucian thought”created“ a myth about Man, ”“ ‘a(chǎn) consciousness of human polarization (ren-jiyi-shi)’....whereby on the one hand there is extreme dissatisfaction with one’s current situation, on the other, the belief that the true condition of ‘Man’ is not just what we can presently think up, what we are accustomed to—that is only the beginning level of human life. The truly good human condition is open without limits [to new possibilities], one can never know what its ultimate limits are.”For Wang, this idea he ascribed to Chang—a Confucian“ ‘consciousness of human polarization’ ”—helps explain why Chinese intellectuals in the 1920s combined their extreme dissatisfaction with China’s current condition with a belief that“socialism”was the key to realizing a perfect society. That is, this“polarization”was a or the major source for the outlook of modern Chinese believers in socialism, who“viewed the society they lived in with extreme contempt, as a dirty state of degeneration, while celebrating the future in extreme terms, a ‘golden age’ created by human beings.”See Wang Fan-sen et al.,Zhong-guojin-daisi-xiang-shi-dezhuan-xingshi-dai:ChangHaoyuan-shiqi-zhizhu-shoulun-wen-ji(Modern Chinese Intellectual History—an Era of Change from One Type to Another Type of Thought and Society: Essays in Honor of Academician Chang’s Seventieth Birthday; Taipei: Lian-jing chu-ban shi-ye gu-fen you-xian gong-si, 2007), p. 197 (below referred to as“Wang Fan-sen”).

    As for premise #3 (the moral hero’s dependence on a supporting cosmic-historical process), Chang in 2004 stated:“the intellectuals of [modern China’s] age of change from one type to another type of thinking and society (zhuan-xingshi-dai) used the idea of history’s irresistible tide (li-shichao-liu) to replace [the Confucian idea] of Heaven’s will, simultaneously retaining the traditional concept of the mind...”Chang also in effect synthesized premises #3 and #4 when he summed up the shared outlook of the modern Chinese intellectual mainstream asyi-shiben-wei-deli-shifa-zhan-lun(a theory viewing historical development as a function of consciousness) (Chang thus mistakenly suggested that all combinations of these two premises took the form of voluntarism, ignored premises #1 and #2, and presented a kind of overview formula that is neither justified as a balanced empirical description nor presented s a recommended philosophical perspective.) I here quote from Max K.W. Huang’s article in Wang Fan-sen, p. 372; Huang quotes from Chang Hao,Shi-dai-detan-suo(Investigations into the Issues of Our Era; Taipei: Academia Sinica, 2004), p. 60.

    In thus essentially if not completely agreeing with my conceptualizations of premises #3 and #4 some twenty-five years previously, Chang reversed his earlier refutations of these conceptualizations. These refutations are in his contribution to the 1980 JAS“review symposium”onEscapefromPredicament. In this latter article of his, he refuted the premise #4 idea that Neo-Confucianism pictured the mind of the self as caught up in a tension or“antinomy”between belief in its boundless, transnatural power and awareness of its powerful tendency toward misunderstanding and moral weakness. He said that this emphasis of mine on“tension,”which indeed ran counter to all previous discussions of Neo-Confucianism, especially those of the New Confucians, actually dealt with a distinction in Neo-Confucianism between the“sense of infinitude”and the“sense of finitude, an awareness of the limitations and evils inherent in finite human beings.”He then argued that“Metzger’s conception of a sense of predicament highlights the sense of finitude and the concomitant antinomy, exposing a dimension of the Neo-Confucian view of the self which was never fully explored before,”but that I had overemphasized the sense of finitude, since it“remained primarily in the background of the Neo-Confucian worldview while the sense of infinitude stood out in the foreground”(review symposium, p. 264). Thus, in his eyes in 1980, the neo-Confucian concept of the self lacked any“sense of predicament,”“antinomy,”or“consciousness of human polarization.”

    In this same 1980 review symposium, Chang also refuted premise #3, which also ran counter to all previous scholarly discussion. Citing an unpublished version of my 1981“Selfhood and Authority in Neo-Confucian Political Culture,”he perspicaciously quoted from it to sum up my thesis:“ In this new secularized context, however, Chinese found it easy to regard history as a vehicle of attributes previously projected unto [my text said ‘onto’] ‘Heaven and earth.’ ”Chang’s objection:“...formal similarities must be distinguished from substantive continuities....Neo-Confucianism and Maoism both link the individual as moral hero to the cosmic-historical process. But they define the moral hero and the cosmic-historical process differently, and consequently offer different interpretations of the relationship between the two. In his highly suggestive discussion of continuities in this context, Metzger sometimes mixes up the two levels and sees formal similarities between Neo-Confucianism and Maoism as substantive continuities”(review symposium, p. 271).

    By at least 2004, therefore, Chang came to agree essentially or wholly with earlier views of mine which he had described in 1980 as suggestive but mistaken. In presenting these new views of his, however, he omitted any mention of the fact that they essentially if not wholly coincided with these earlier views of mine, not to mention saying that he had come to believe that these earlier views of mine were basically correct, and that, in 1980, it was he, not I, who had been mistaken.

    His position in 2008, when I for the first time encountered his 2004 text and raised this question with him, was that he indeed had failed in 1980 properly to assess my views and had later come to accept them. Moreover, he acknowledged in general terms that my writings and numberless discussions with him over the years had greatly influenced his work, noting that he had made this general point in the“Acknowledgements”section of hisChineseIntellectualsinCrisis(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987), p. x. He did not, however, agree that he had transferred any specific ideas from my publications into his. He firmly stated that when he came to reverse his judgment about premises #3 and #4, he did not do so by concluding that ideas of mine he had previously viewed as wrong were really not wrong. Instead, he said, he had independently developed similar if not identical ideas. Therefore, he held, he acted appropriately when he presented these new ideas of his as his own without any mention that they coincided with those which I had earlier developed, and which he had originally refuted. It was enough, he said, that he acknowledged my influence on his work in general terms.

    As he put it in an undated letter I received around May 1, 2008,“It is true that I didn’t do justice to the insightfulness of your idea of escape from predicament which we debated in JAS in the late 1970s. The reason as I now look back at this episode is that at the time I didn’t penetrate beyond your heavy language to see the larger point you were making. Some years later I finally came around to a notion of the complexity and internal tension in the Chinese tradition by way of Eric Voegelin, [thexin-ru’s] [Chang here used Chinese logographs for ‘New Confucians’]...concept of transcendence inward and the history of religion approach. This finally allowed me to see the insightfulness and power of your notion of ‘escape from predicament.’ ”

    With regard to premise #3 (the modern replacement of the Neo-Confucian“Heaven”with the idea of“history”to articulate the moral hero’s dependence on a supporting cosmic-historical force), Chang in a letter to me of May 23, 2008 said:“Regarding the idea that history played a function to self in modern thought similar to that played by [tian] or [tian-ming] [the letter here used Chinese logographs for ‘Heaven’ and ‘Heaven’s Mandate’]...in relation to self in traditional thought, my memory told me I didn’t get it from your article cited in your letter, simply because I didn’t read your article.”

    When I wrote him pointing out that he had cited an unpublished version of this very article of mine in his contribution to the 1980 JAS review symposium and there had precisely described and refuted my thesis in this article (review symposium, p. 271), Chang replied in a letter of June 12, 2008:“Regarding my idea of modern Chinese intellectuals’ combination of Confucian [ren-benyi-shi] [Chang here used Chinese logographs I translate as ‘a(chǎn) consciousness putting primacy on the nature of human existence’]...and moral activism with teleological history reminiscent of the Confucian idea of [self/Heaven] [Chang here used the logographs for ‘my mind/Heaven’], I stand by what I said before. The main reason is that this idea grows organically out of my previous writings which I asked you to review before making accusations.”He then referred to hisChineseIntellectualsinCrisis, which was published in 1987, some seven years after he read my“Selfhood and Authority in Neo-Confucian Culture,”encountered and quoted my statement in it that Chinese in modern times“ ‘found it easy to regard history as a vehicle of attributes previously projected onto“Heaven and Earth”’ ”(“Selfhood and Authority,”p. 16, review symposium, p. 271), viewed this idea as“highly suggestive,”and then rejected it as confusing“formal similarities”with“substantive continuities”(ibid.).

    His point apparently was that after he encountered and refuted this idea of mine in 1980, it dropped out of his mind while he worked on the manuscript he published in 1987 and arrived at the same idea. His letter of June 12, 2008 continued: trying in the 1980s“to explain how [Kang You-wei] was able to combine the Confucian idea of moral vanguard and the concomitant moral-political activism with his developmental and utopian view of history,”he independently arrived at the insight that, for Kang, history played essentially the same role“heaven”played for Neo-Confucians. He then was able, again independently, to see how this concept of Kang’s became incorporated into the outlook of China’s intellectual mainstream as a whole in the twentieth century.

    Apparently, Chang also believed he had independently arrived at a new insight when he used“a consciousness of human polarization”to describe the Neo-Confucian concept of the self, where I had spoken inEscapefromPredicamentof a tension or“antinomy”(as he put it in 1980) between“a transnatural ability to tap the beneficent, transcendent cosmic force impinging on the naturally given mind and organically shaping the world outside”and“a massive tendency toward moral failure based on inescapable cosmic conditions which [Neo-Confucians] could all too easily sense in their own individual minds”(Escape, pp. 123, 158).

    It is of course not uncommon for students of history independently to reach the same conclusion. It is, however, at the very least rare for an exceptionally intelligent and erudite scholar to encounter a thesis proposed by an old, close friend who admittedly has much influenced him; to regard this thesis as“highly suggestive”; to take the pains to refute it; to lose all memory of it while independently arriving at a thesis coinciding with it; and then to present this thesis as his own original insight to a Chinese audience uninformed about or uninterested in the earlier secondary literature.

    My view is that Professor Chang undoubtedly was persuaded by his own work on Kang’s ideas that they entailed the above equation of history with Heaven as a force supporting the moral hero. I do not, however, believe that my earlier recognition of this equation had disappeared from his mind as he came to think of this equation, which I had systematically analyzed in the lead article of a prominent essay collection. Nor do I believe that when he devised the term“a consciousness of human polarization,”his own consciousness was empty of any memory of that“antinomy”which I had at great length analyzed as central to the Neo-Confucian concept of the self, an analysis he had so carefully refuted in 1980. Moreover, to whatever extent Chang’s conclusions regarding premises #3 and #4 were reached independently, it was incumbent on him as a scrupulous scholar respecting the work of colleagues to make clear in his published texts the extent to which these conclusions of his coincided with and indeed confirmed the conclusions reached earlier by another student of the subject, not to mention acknowledging such earlier conclusions when he originally had objected to them.

    猜你喜歡
    墨子
    徽州墨子酥系列包裝設(shè)計
    包裝工程(2024年8期)2024-04-23 04:05:02
    Less Speech, More Essence多言何益
    “武圣人,惟墨子足以當(dāng)之”——馮友蘭武圣觀論析
    墨子破云梯
    墨子訓(xùn)徒
    墨子教誨青年
    墨子教誨青年
    “墨子號”與墨子
    兒童時代(2017年14期)2017-10-13 08:14:34
    “墨子”飛天 中國領(lǐng)跑
    《墨子》“戮于社”考——兼談社的文化功能
    東方考古(2016年0期)2016-07-31 17:45:44
    婷婷色综合大香蕉| 少妇 在线观看| 91字幕亚洲| 国产精品国产av在线观看| 天天添夜夜摸| 亚洲国产av新网站| 我的亚洲天堂| 亚洲午夜精品一区,二区,三区| av在线app专区| 99re6热这里在线精品视频| 精品福利永久在线观看| 国产精品亚洲av一区麻豆| 一区二区三区四区激情视频| 激情视频va一区二区三区| 国产一区有黄有色的免费视频| 成人亚洲精品一区在线观看| 麻豆国产av国片精品| xxx大片免费视频| av国产久精品久网站免费入址| 婷婷成人精品国产| 亚洲精品美女久久久久99蜜臀 | 婷婷成人精品国产| 99国产精品免费福利视频| 少妇粗大呻吟视频| 日本五十路高清| 国产欧美日韩精品亚洲av| 18在线观看网站| 久久久精品94久久精品| 亚洲欧美中文字幕日韩二区| 国产真人三级小视频在线观看| 国产精品av久久久久免费| 精品国产乱码久久久久久小说| 精品一区二区三区av网在线观看 | 成人影院久久| 丰满饥渴人妻一区二区三| 国产精品久久久人人做人人爽| 大型av网站在线播放| 首页视频小说图片口味搜索 | 天天躁夜夜躁狠狠久久av| 少妇人妻久久综合中文| 我要看黄色一级片免费的| 亚洲精品国产区一区二| 人人妻,人人澡人人爽秒播 | 2018国产大陆天天弄谢| 男男h啪啪无遮挡| 每晚都被弄得嗷嗷叫到高潮| 国产在线视频一区二区| 亚洲天堂av无毛| 9色porny在线观看| 午夜视频精品福利| 亚洲av电影在线进入| 精品一区二区三区四区五区乱码 | 尾随美女入室| 日本av免费视频播放| 青春草亚洲视频在线观看| 亚洲专区国产一区二区| 男女床上黄色一级片免费看| 别揉我奶头~嗯~啊~动态视频 | 久久久久久人人人人人| 午夜福利在线免费观看网站| 久久久久久亚洲精品国产蜜桃av| 老司机亚洲免费影院| tube8黄色片| 国产熟女欧美一区二区| av网站在线播放免费| 欧美国产精品va在线观看不卡| 国产亚洲av片在线观看秒播厂| 人体艺术视频欧美日本| e午夜精品久久久久久久| 王馨瑶露胸无遮挡在线观看| 欧美精品高潮呻吟av久久| 国产亚洲精品久久久久5区| 七月丁香在线播放| 欧美国产精品va在线观看不卡| 国产又爽黄色视频| 日韩av不卡免费在线播放| 国产成人啪精品午夜网站| 国产精品久久久久久精品电影小说| av欧美777| 精品福利永久在线观看| 久久午夜综合久久蜜桃| 久久久久久久大尺度免费视频| 亚洲精品一二三| 成在线人永久免费视频| 国产福利在线免费观看视频| 欧美亚洲 丝袜 人妻 在线| 男女下面插进去视频免费观看| 香蕉国产在线看| 99久久精品国产亚洲精品| 日本一区二区免费在线视频| 国产成人免费观看mmmm| 大片电影免费在线观看免费| 国产精品三级大全| 激情五月婷婷亚洲| 美女福利国产在线| 亚洲午夜精品一区,二区,三区| 老汉色∧v一级毛片| 丁香六月天网| 亚洲精品美女久久av网站| 免费人妻精品一区二区三区视频| 国产成人啪精品午夜网站| 久久人人爽人人片av| 亚洲,欧美精品.| 男人操女人黄网站| 国语对白做爰xxxⅹ性视频网站| 国产亚洲av片在线观看秒播厂| 亚洲欧美精品自产自拍| 9色porny在线观看| 精品人妻一区二区三区麻豆| 欧美精品一区二区大全| 黑人猛操日本美女一级片| 午夜两性在线视频| 国产亚洲欧美在线一区二区| 国产一区二区在线观看av| 又黄又粗又硬又大视频| 国产主播在线观看一区二区 | 国产成人欧美| 欧美日韩福利视频一区二区| 一本大道久久a久久精品| 国产精品久久久av美女十八| 亚洲人成电影观看| 丁香六月欧美| 无遮挡黄片免费观看| 满18在线观看网站| 久久ye,这里只有精品| 亚洲精品中文字幕在线视频| 叶爱在线成人免费视频播放| 日本vs欧美在线观看视频| 丰满少妇做爰视频| 国产欧美日韩一区二区三 | 菩萨蛮人人尽说江南好唐韦庄| 女人爽到高潮嗷嗷叫在线视频| 日韩视频在线欧美| 国产精品国产三级专区第一集| 激情五月婷婷亚洲| 乱人伦中国视频| 亚洲av日韩在线播放| 午夜久久久在线观看| 久久人人爽人人片av| 看免费成人av毛片| 啦啦啦在线观看免费高清www| 国产精品一区二区精品视频观看| 1024香蕉在线观看| 午夜老司机福利片| 狂野欧美激情性bbbbbb| 国产高清不卡午夜福利| 丰满迷人的少妇在线观看| 999久久久国产精品视频| 国产av精品麻豆| 亚洲综合色网址| 建设人人有责人人尽责人人享有的| 日本黄色日本黄色录像| 亚洲综合色网址| 丰满饥渴人妻一区二区三| 成人亚洲精品一区在线观看| 欧美精品av麻豆av| 久久人人97超碰香蕉20202| 国产免费福利视频在线观看| 国产99久久九九免费精品| 男女午夜视频在线观看| 欧美精品一区二区免费开放| 免费在线观看视频国产中文字幕亚洲 | 精品国产一区二区三区四区第35| 国产精品一国产av| 热99国产精品久久久久久7| 18禁国产床啪视频网站| 女人精品久久久久毛片| 婷婷色av中文字幕| 大型av网站在线播放| 50天的宝宝边吃奶边哭怎么回事| 亚洲成人免费av在线播放| 视频在线观看一区二区三区| 精品国产国语对白av| 青春草视频在线免费观看| 日韩一本色道免费dvd| 亚洲成国产人片在线观看| 欧美日韩精品网址| 人人妻人人爽人人添夜夜欢视频| 欧美亚洲 丝袜 人妻 在线| 国产成人精品久久二区二区免费| 久热这里只有精品99| 波多野结衣一区麻豆| 夜夜骑夜夜射夜夜干| 欧美变态另类bdsm刘玥| 亚洲av男天堂| 欧美 日韩 精品 国产| 少妇裸体淫交视频免费看高清 | 国产99久久九九免费精品| 少妇精品久久久久久久| 欧美精品一区二区免费开放| 精品福利观看| 最近中文字幕2019免费版| 夫妻午夜视频| 女人高潮潮喷娇喘18禁视频| 两性夫妻黄色片| 中文字幕精品免费在线观看视频| 国产在线视频一区二区| 男女国产视频网站| 搡老岳熟女国产| 亚洲熟女精品中文字幕| 美女国产高潮福利片在线看| 成人免费观看视频高清| 美女扒开内裤让男人捅视频| av在线app专区| 大香蕉久久成人网| 免费无遮挡裸体视频| 国产亚洲欧美在线一区二区| 男女那种视频在线观看| 午夜福利18| 成年人黄色毛片网站| 熟妇人妻久久中文字幕3abv| 欧美黄色片欧美黄色片| 亚洲国产精品久久男人天堂| 久久欧美精品欧美久久欧美| 国产av又大| 亚洲国产精品合色在线| 国产精品自产拍在线观看55亚洲| 正在播放国产对白刺激| 国产不卡一卡二| 免费在线观看黄色视频的| 亚洲一区中文字幕在线| 亚洲狠狠婷婷综合久久图片| 高清在线国产一区| 日韩 欧美 亚洲 中文字幕| 精品熟女少妇八av免费久了| 亚洲 欧美 日韩 在线 免费| 欧美黑人巨大hd| 久久国产亚洲av麻豆专区| 久久婷婷人人爽人人干人人爱| 99热6这里只有精品| 欧美日韩精品网址| 午夜福利免费观看在线| 91老司机精品| 草草在线视频免费看| 中文字幕人妻熟女乱码| 一区二区三区激情视频| 狠狠狠狠99中文字幕| 一级毛片精品| 中文字幕人妻丝袜一区二区| 天堂影院成人在线观看| 日本 av在线| 人人妻人人澡人人看| 黄色成人免费大全| 欧美zozozo另类| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜添小说| 午夜福利一区二区在线看| xxxwww97欧美| 亚洲电影在线观看av| 国产高清有码在线观看视频 | 曰老女人黄片| 亚洲九九香蕉| 精品卡一卡二卡四卡免费| 一a级毛片在线观看| 午夜激情福利司机影院| 色哟哟哟哟哟哟| 夜夜爽天天搞| 超碰成人久久| 国内毛片毛片毛片毛片毛片| 午夜日韩欧美国产| 哪里可以看免费的av片| 中文在线观看免费www的网站 | 亚洲精品中文字幕一二三四区| 国产精品野战在线观看| 深夜精品福利| 国内久久婷婷六月综合欲色啪| 色在线成人网| 中文字幕精品亚洲无线码一区 | 操出白浆在线播放| 国产一级毛片七仙女欲春2 | 久久久久亚洲av毛片大全| 给我免费播放毛片高清在线观看| 麻豆成人av在线观看| 中文字幕另类日韩欧美亚洲嫩草| netflix在线观看网站| 日韩欧美三级三区| svipshipincom国产片| 国产野战对白在线观看| 黄色片一级片一级黄色片| 亚洲成人免费电影在线观看| 欧美成人一区二区免费高清观看 | 久久 成人 亚洲| 国产精品久久久人人做人人爽| 国产精品亚洲av一区麻豆| 精品电影一区二区在线| 后天国语完整版免费观看| 成年版毛片免费区| 最近最新中文字幕大全免费视频| 免费在线观看视频国产中文字幕亚洲| 俄罗斯特黄特色一大片| 久久精品国产综合久久久| 日韩三级视频一区二区三区| 久久青草综合色| 香蕉av资源在线| 91麻豆av在线| 久久国产乱子伦精品免费另类| 99精品久久久久人妻精品| 亚洲五月色婷婷综合| 天天添夜夜摸| 在线观看舔阴道视频| 在线天堂中文资源库| 一本精品99久久精品77| av欧美777| 国产亚洲欧美98| 999久久久国产精品视频| 亚洲成av人片免费观看| 欧美日韩黄片免| www.www免费av| 亚洲色图av天堂| 精品免费久久久久久久清纯| 国产成+人综合+亚洲专区| 亚洲无线在线观看| 午夜日韩欧美国产| 嫩草影院精品99| 国产激情偷乱视频一区二区| 国产精品九九99| 高潮久久久久久久久久久不卡| av在线播放免费不卡| www国产在线视频色| 日本五十路高清| 热99re8久久精品国产| 国产一区二区三区视频了| 国产成人影院久久av| 国产精品98久久久久久宅男小说| 51午夜福利影视在线观看| 韩国av一区二区三区四区| 久久久久久久午夜电影| 看黄色毛片网站| 久久精品影院6| 天堂影院成人在线观看| 亚洲,欧美精品.| 国产片内射在线| 一区二区日韩欧美中文字幕| 国产成人啪精品午夜网站| 精品国产一区二区三区四区第35| 亚洲精品国产一区二区精华液| 一级a爱片免费观看的视频| 久久久精品国产亚洲av高清涩受| 午夜免费成人在线视频| 最新在线观看一区二区三区| 美女大奶头视频| av片东京热男人的天堂| 亚洲真实伦在线观看| 国产精品美女特级片免费视频播放器 | 精品久久久久久久久久免费视频| 欧美激情 高清一区二区三区| 伦理电影免费视频| 亚洲成人国产一区在线观看| 久久国产精品人妻蜜桃| 亚洲精品美女久久久久99蜜臀| 久久久久久久久免费视频了| 天堂√8在线中文| 人妻丰满熟妇av一区二区三区| 亚洲第一青青草原| 精品国产乱子伦一区二区三区| 欧美黑人欧美精品刺激| 99精品在免费线老司机午夜| 色综合站精品国产| 韩国av一区二区三区四区| 嫩草影院精品99| 黑人操中国人逼视频| 亚洲人成77777在线视频| 看黄色毛片网站| 淫秽高清视频在线观看| 人人妻人人看人人澡| 亚洲熟妇中文字幕五十中出| 精品国内亚洲2022精品成人| 欧美日韩中文字幕国产精品一区二区三区| 中文字幕高清在线视频| 亚洲av电影在线进入| 99久久99久久久精品蜜桃| 久久香蕉国产精品| 黑人操中国人逼视频| 亚洲狠狠婷婷综合久久图片| 亚洲自偷自拍图片 自拍| 嫩草影院精品99| 国产熟女xx| 日韩欧美免费精品| 亚洲午夜精品一区,二区,三区| 69av精品久久久久久| 曰老女人黄片| 18禁裸乳无遮挡免费网站照片 | 欧美zozozo另类| 手机成人av网站| 国产精品 国内视频| 国产精品国产高清国产av| 中文字幕另类日韩欧美亚洲嫩草| 欧美激情久久久久久爽电影| 免费看十八禁软件| 午夜两性在线视频| 亚洲一卡2卡3卡4卡5卡精品中文| 久久欧美精品欧美久久欧美| 国产成人欧美在线观看| 久久亚洲精品不卡| 观看免费一级毛片| 亚洲成av片中文字幕在线观看| 人妻丰满熟妇av一区二区三区| 在线天堂中文资源库| 真人做人爱边吃奶动态| 黑丝袜美女国产一区| 在线观看舔阴道视频| 少妇裸体淫交视频免费看高清 | 亚洲精品中文字幕在线视频| 99久久国产精品久久久| 亚洲国产毛片av蜜桃av| 午夜福利成人在线免费观看| 欧美午夜高清在线| 亚洲欧美日韩高清在线视频| 90打野战视频偷拍视频| 99国产精品一区二区三区| 欧美在线一区亚洲| 黑人巨大精品欧美一区二区mp4| 国产精华一区二区三区| 18禁观看日本| 免费在线观看成人毛片| 91成人精品电影| 久久精品国产99精品国产亚洲性色| 国产一区在线观看成人免费| 日韩欧美国产在线观看| 99在线人妻在线中文字幕| 亚洲中文日韩欧美视频| 亚洲七黄色美女视频| 欧美精品亚洲一区二区| 一区二区三区精品91| 免费在线观看影片大全网站| 99久久精品国产亚洲精品| 丁香欧美五月| 色尼玛亚洲综合影院| 亚洲第一青青草原| 99国产精品99久久久久| 亚洲av第一区精品v没综合| 国语自产精品视频在线第100页| 又大又爽又粗| 精品电影一区二区在线| 狂野欧美激情性xxxx| 中文字幕人成人乱码亚洲影| 亚洲天堂国产精品一区在线| 亚洲精品美女久久av网站| 亚洲av成人一区二区三| cao死你这个sao货| 国产99白浆流出| 无人区码免费观看不卡| 国产一区在线观看成人免费| 成人18禁高潮啪啪吃奶动态图| 国产精品爽爽va在线观看网站 | 亚洲精品国产精品久久久不卡| 一区二区三区国产精品乱码| 欧美日韩乱码在线| 一级黄色大片毛片| 亚洲人成电影免费在线| 在线视频色国产色| 中文字幕最新亚洲高清| 欧美日韩中文字幕国产精品一区二区三区| 不卡av一区二区三区| 午夜亚洲福利在线播放| 国产精品98久久久久久宅男小说| 好男人在线观看高清免费视频 | 操出白浆在线播放| 97人妻精品一区二区三区麻豆 | 在线视频色国产色| 国产片内射在线| 亚洲精品美女久久av网站| 国产亚洲精品av在线| 亚洲av第一区精品v没综合| 又紧又爽又黄一区二区| 国产极品粉嫩免费观看在线| 欧美在线黄色| 91大片在线观看| 亚洲中文av在线| 国产熟女xx| 亚洲国产欧美一区二区综合| 99久久久亚洲精品蜜臀av| 夜夜夜夜夜久久久久| 一区二区日韩欧美中文字幕| 国产精品电影一区二区三区| 国产伦人伦偷精品视频| 亚洲中文字幕日韩| 欧美色欧美亚洲另类二区| 巨乳人妻的诱惑在线观看| 高清在线国产一区| 女性生殖器流出的白浆| 久久久久国产精品人妻aⅴ院| 久久久久国内视频| 韩国精品一区二区三区| 国产精品久久电影中文字幕| 亚洲熟妇中文字幕五十中出| 无限看片的www在线观看| 亚洲国产欧美一区二区综合| 欧美一区二区精品小视频在线| 国产精品亚洲av一区麻豆| 色综合亚洲欧美另类图片| 黄色毛片三级朝国网站| 欧美日韩亚洲综合一区二区三区_| 曰老女人黄片| 国产真实乱freesex| 国产精品久久久av美女十八| 日本一本二区三区精品| 天天添夜夜摸| 女同久久另类99精品国产91| 久久这里只有精品19| 亚洲国产看品久久| 怎么达到女性高潮| 黄频高清免费视频| 国产一级毛片七仙女欲春2 | 免费电影在线观看免费观看| 波多野结衣巨乳人妻| 亚洲国产精品成人综合色| 免费在线观看影片大全网站| 99久久综合精品五月天人人| www.999成人在线观看| 在线观看舔阴道视频| 18美女黄网站色大片免费观看| 天天躁夜夜躁狠狠躁躁| 法律面前人人平等表现在哪些方面| 欧美黑人欧美精品刺激| 亚洲自偷自拍图片 自拍| 一区二区三区精品91| 亚洲精品一区av在线观看| 正在播放国产对白刺激| 嫩草影院精品99| 久热爱精品视频在线9| 欧美日韩一级在线毛片| 午夜a级毛片| 日日爽夜夜爽网站| 国产高清有码在线观看视频 | 亚洲欧美日韩无卡精品| 天堂影院成人在线观看| 国产精品精品国产色婷婷| av免费在线观看网站| av福利片在线| 国产主播在线观看一区二区| 99国产精品99久久久久| 午夜福利在线观看吧| 波多野结衣高清无吗| 国产精品永久免费网站| 91成年电影在线观看| 白带黄色成豆腐渣| 国产精品美女特级片免费视频播放器 | 欧美精品啪啪一区二区三区| 久9热在线精品视频| 国产一区在线观看成人免费| 日日夜夜操网爽| 人成视频在线观看免费观看| 色哟哟哟哟哟哟| 欧美成人免费av一区二区三区| АⅤ资源中文在线天堂| 曰老女人黄片| bbb黄色大片| 婷婷六月久久综合丁香| 国产亚洲精品综合一区在线观看 | 亚洲人成网站高清观看| 亚洲av第一区精品v没综合| 黄色 视频免费看| 校园春色视频在线观看| 成人免费观看视频高清| 麻豆成人av在线观看| e午夜精品久久久久久久| 亚洲av美国av| 色婷婷久久久亚洲欧美| 麻豆国产av国片精品| 午夜a级毛片| 国产成人精品久久二区二区免费| 亚洲精华国产精华精| 午夜免费成人在线视频| 久久热在线av| 成人午夜高清在线视频 | www国产在线视频色| 天堂√8在线中文| 老司机在亚洲福利影院| 很黄的视频免费| 99热只有精品国产| 欧美性长视频在线观看| 亚洲成人久久爱视频| 他把我摸到了高潮在线观看| 久久精品亚洲精品国产色婷小说| 91国产中文字幕| 日韩 欧美 亚洲 中文字幕| 精品久久久久久久人妻蜜臀av| 男女视频在线观看网站免费 | 欧美日韩亚洲综合一区二区三区_| 在线观看www视频免费| 少妇的丰满在线观看| 欧美激情极品国产一区二区三区| 一二三四在线观看免费中文在| 成年免费大片在线观看| 长腿黑丝高跟| 黄色成人免费大全| 欧美丝袜亚洲另类 | 国产精品久久久久久精品电影 | 久久久久九九精品影院| 亚洲第一av免费看| 久久国产亚洲av麻豆专区| 18禁裸乳无遮挡免费网站照片 | 免费在线观看亚洲国产| 亚洲精品色激情综合| 手机成人av网站| aaaaa片日本免费| 亚洲久久久国产精品| 国语自产精品视频在线第100页| 国产日本99.免费观看| 亚洲熟妇中文字幕五十中出| 777久久人妻少妇嫩草av网站| av片东京热男人的天堂| 国产av不卡久久| 精品福利观看| 亚洲一区高清亚洲精品| 亚洲熟妇熟女久久| 侵犯人妻中文字幕一二三四区| www国产在线视频色| 国产亚洲欧美在线一区二区| 成人特级黄色片久久久久久久| 成人亚洲精品av一区二区| 日韩视频一区二区在线观看| 黄色 视频免费看| 国产高清videossex| 国产高清有码在线观看视频 |