• <tr id="yyy80"></tr>
  • <sup id="yyy80"></sup>
  • <tfoot id="yyy80"><noscript id="yyy80"></noscript></tfoot>
  • 99热精品在线国产_美女午夜性视频免费_国产精品国产高清国产av_av欧美777_自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇_亚洲熟女精品中文字幕_www日本黄色视频网_国产精品野战在线观看 ?

    Confucius, Mencius, and Xunzi on Yu: Differential Confucian Theories of Yu in Light of the Desire Theory in Contemporary Western Ethics

    2021-11-07 00:51:05LiuYuedi
    孔學堂 2021年3期

    Liu Yuedi

    Abstract: In the terms of Western categorizations of desire, Confuciuss theory of yu (desire) accounts for both its subjective and objective, constituting an integral structure of “desiring benevolence and attaining it,” without a clear choice between good and evil. Menciuss theory of yu, stressing “completing the mind to know ones nature,” is more inclined toward the objective implications of desire. It concerns motivated desire and aims to provide reason for moral actions toward goodness. Xunzi argues that “human nature can be improved through such moral means as ritual,” and his theory basically focuses on subjective and unmotivated desires. Though common human desires are associated with evil, people can be enculturated to good effect by external transformation through ritual and the minds faculty of inclining to goodness. From these different theories there emerge two tendencies: Menciuss top-down model of “good mind—good nature—good emotions,” and Xunzis bottom-up model of “evil emotions—evil nature—good mind.” Early Confucian theories of yu reflect a Chinese “emotion–reason structure,” which trascends the dichotomy of subjective and objective desires and resolves the contradiction between emotionalism and rationalism as well, thus making it possible to return to roots and open a new, integrated approach to such fundamental issues as desire.

    Keywords: yu, desire benevolence and attain it, who commands desire is good, human desire shared by all alike

    In early Confucian texts, Confucius, Mencius, and Xunzi all dwelt on yu 欲 (desire), but they each proposed different theories, calling for our discretion when analyzing them. This paper focuses on their theories of yu from the perspective of comparative philosophy. In contemporary Western ethics, the issue of desire has been explored deeply in a brand-new way. The general theoretical logic in its studies is that when we desire X and we believe that we can get X by doing Y, and then we will do Y. However, this analytical philosophical approach is still an instance of rational analysis. In this regard, todays mainstream attempt is to justify internal rational support for desire, which is concerned with the relationship between desire and motivation or motive.

    Conceptual Distinction between Motivation and Motive

    [Refer to page 81 for Chinese. Similarly hereinafter]

    To the Chinese word dongji 動機, there are in English at least two corresponding words: motivation and motive. Here we make a tentative distinction between them in concept: “motivation” means the intention which causes an act, while “motive” denotes the incentive which actuates an act. The former refers to the intention behind a possible act and the latter, to activating an actual act, so their difference is between the non-actual and the actual in that an internal intention to do something is, after all, not an actual doing of it, and unconscious action is not necessarily in need of conscious intention as its precursor. For the time being, this distinction seems to have become a certain new consensus, though, in China, many general studies of this topic have not made such a distinction within the concept of dongji and consequently lagged behind due to their attachment to the outdated dichotomy of dongji and act.

    Having distinguished between the two types of dongji, when we try to match them with types of desire, we find that the value of distinguishing between motivation and motive becomes more salient, which is highly inspirational to us in our attempt to approach emotion from the angle of dongji. For example, in the final analysis, are such emotions as the feeling of compassion, as moral impetus, motivated or actualized? Probably it involves both at the same time. In this sense, the moral situation of “people suddenly seeing a child about to fall into a well” which Mencius proposes involves potentially intentional desire, for the people intend to save the child. This is a performative action, which aims to realize an act which people intend or desire. But the question is, how on earth can such intention or desire for saving can turn into moral act? This question has to do with the deep relationship between dongji and desire. In relation to dongji, desire is logically necessary, but its function is yet to be investigated. Here, Thomas Nagel, contemporary American philosopher, gives such a conclusion: “The fact that the presence of a desire is a logically necessary condition (because it is a logical consequence) of a reasons motivating, does not entail that it is a necessary condition of the presence of the reason; and if it is motivated by that reason it cannot be among the reasons conditions.” This conclusion, actually, elevates the position of desire in the moral dongji, and at the same time provides a condition for it. Thus, this suggests that the in-depth relationship between desire and dongji needs requires ultimate distinction and definition.

    Classification of Desires: Based on Dongji, Reason, and the Subjective–Objective Dichotomy [82]

    Contemporary Western scholars of the philosophy of emotion tend to hold that human emotions are more likely related to motivations rather than motives. Now that motivations and motives have first been distinguished conceptually, how do they match types of human desire? This involves Nagels basic classification of human desires. Nagel does not agree with David Hume (1711–1776) and his followers, who are of the general opinion that an act must be activated by a desire; rather, Nagel classifies desires into motivated desires and unmotivated desires. He cites an example to illustrate it: Hunger belongs to the unmotivated desires in the sense that the desire which occurs directly in the human body is unmotivated, and when one feels hungry, it is caused by lack of food, but not motivated by it. What then does the motivated desire mean? If one opens a fridge only to find no food, driven by the feeling of hunger, one will go shopping for food. Such a desire as involves the actors resolution and discretion belongs to motivated desire.

    As Nagel considers more comprehensively, “The assumption that a motivating desire underlies every intentional act depends, I believe, on confusion between two sorts of desires, motivated and unmotivated.” In my opinion, this is an important distinction. Informed by the difference between motivated and unmotivated desires, the former corresponding to motivations and the latter to motives. These are the two types of desires defined on the basis of dongji.

    The claim that a desire underlies every act is true only if desires are taken to include motivated as well as unmotivated desires, and it is true only in the sense that whatever may be the motivation for someones intentional pursuit of a goal, it becomes in virtue of his pursuit ipso facto appropriate to ascribe to him a desire for that goal.

    Therefore, when a desire can activate an act, it must be motivated, and so is a motive. When a desire cannot activate any act, it is unmotivated and so is a motivation, since it cannot turn directly into an action, and this is the fundamental standard for the distinguishing between the two types.

    In Nagels famous work The Possibility of Altruism (1979), he adopts a simpler distinction, namely distinguishing between different types of desires by reference to subjective reason and objective reason. On the basis of this standard, there are simply two types of desires: subjective desires and objective desires. Here Nagel seems to say that subjective desires are defined by personal standpoint and objective desires by impersonal standpoint. As he says, “All of the persons in a situation, and all of the viewpoints, expectations, and conditions of evidence associated with them, fall within a single impersonal conception.” Thus when he refers to “an inability to make practical judgments about other persons in the same sense in which one can make them in ones own case,” this involves the more complicated issue of equality with other persons. In fact, when he clarifies his argumentation for the universality of reason, Nagel is concerned not only with the above-mentioned objective reason, that is, its universality is not subject to person, but also with timeless reason, that is, that universality is not subject to time, and these two aspects can coexist in the same one action.

    As regards the classification of desires, Nagels conflict between the subjective and the objective follows Derek Parfits (1942–2017) understanding that “the claims of objectivity are, here, the claims of intersubjectivity.” Nonetheless, this inference involving the person is in fact not wrong. Nagels objectivity is meanwhile a kind of intersubjectivity, for the objective desire is to be realized among the subjects. Regrettably, though, Nagel attributes a certain absolute universality to objective reason, firmly believing that everyone, at their impersonal standpoint, possesses act–activating power, and only in this way can he lay a firmer objective foundation for his so-called “altruism.” This, clearly, serves his ethical argument and The Possibility of Altruism is also a theoretical defense of his proposition that only objective reason can be acceptable. Though to what extent this defense can be effective is still a moot point, Nagels desire classification on the basis of the subjective–objective dichotomy is quite insightful.

    Taking in all the above Western arguments, we sum up the types of desire classified on the basis of dongji, reason, and the subjective–objective dichotomy and their correspondences with the types of dongji in the following table.

    The purpose of teasing out the desire theories in the Western moral philosophy from the viewpoint of comparative philosophy in the above section is to reflect and review the original texts of Confucianism and, particularly, Confucius, Mencius, and Xunzis theories of yu.

    In the received version of the Analects, the Chinese character yu appears 42 times, and in its meaning, it also conveys rich orientations and dimensions. In many places, Confucius uses the character in the sense of “desire,” “wish,” “intend,” and “prefer.” For example, he might say of a given object that “men may not desire to use it,” “the workman, who wishes to do his work well, must first sharpen his tools” (Analects 15:10), or “Zigong 子貢 (Duanmu Ci 端木賜, 520–456 BCE) intended to do away with the offering of a sheep connected with the inauguration of the first day of each month” (3:17). Confuciuss use of yu also has to do with speaking. For example he says, “The junzi 君子 (man of noble character) wishes to be slow in his speech and earnest in his conduct” (4:24), “I would prefer not speaking” (17:19), and “[Confucius] intended to converse with him” (18:5). But all these examples are irrelevant to morality.

    There are also some passages in the Analects where Confucius uses yu to refer to subjective desires, that is, motivated and reason-following desires. An example is his reference to “pursuing what one desires without being covetous” (20:2). Confucius opposes inconstant love or hate, and either this love or this hate is related to yu, as illustrated by his saying, “You love a man and wish him to live; you hate him and wish him to die. Having wished him to live, you also wish him to die. This is a case of delusion” (12:10). When Jikangzi 季康子 (d. 468 BCE), distressed about the number of thieves in the state, asked him for advice, Confucius said, “If you, sir, were not covetous, though you should reward them to do it, they would not steal” (12:18). Zhu Xi 朱熹 (1130–1200) annotates that answer from Confucius this way: “It means that if Jikangzi were free of greed and desire, even if he offered rewards to them and encouraged them to steal, they would be conscious of shame and refuse to do it.” This indicates that desire usually is connected with covetousness.

    The concept of subjective desire also finds expression in Confuciuss phrase “what the mind (xin 心) desires,” which is of more importance. His well-known saying that “I could follow what my mind desired, without transgressing what was right” (2:4) points to the ultimate realm of moral freedom. However, to ordinary people, such a lofty realm is hardly accessible. So in most cases Confucius talks about desire with an eye to reality. For example, “Riches and honors are what men desire” (4:5). Here, he affirms the legitimacy of the desire for riches and honors and meanwhile notes that the key to gaining riches and honors is gaining them in the right way. When he says “The junzi does not, even for the space of a single meal, act contrary to benevolence (ren 仁). In moments of haste, he cleaves to it. In seasons of danger, he cleaves to it” (ibid.), this refers to a relatively higher level in pursuit of morality. It breaks through the confinement of instinctive desire and meanwhile never deviates from benevolence at any moment. While affirming human desire, Confucius emphasizes the conscious effort to sublimate it. Thus, Qu Boyu 蘧伯玉 “wishes to make his faults few, but he has not yet succeeded” (14:25), which describes the difficult process of attaining moral sublimation.

    There are also some cases in which yu becomes the object of Confuciuss direct denial. They indicate his view of “not desire” (buyu 不欲). Though “not desire” seems to deny desire, it cannot be understood that simplistically. When Confucius says “not to do to others as you would not desire done to yourself” (12:2), the point lies in what is the object of that “not desire.” Obviously, the object of the “not desire” is negative, but that of “my mind desired” in the aforementioned phrase “I could follow what my mind desired” is positive. Therefore, the objects in these two examples are not correspondent. This shows precisely that the objects of yu in the Analects may be positive or negative, and even in some contexts whether they are positive or negative is hard to say. Another example is “Zigong said, ‘What I do not desire men to do to me, I also desire not to do to men. The Master said, ‘Ci, you have not attained that” (5:12). Here, the “not desire” and “desire” are opposite and mutually denying, and whether they refer to positive or negative objects is not clear.

    When talking about such a moral quality as firmness, the negative desire and positive firmness are mentioned as a pair of opposites. In the Analects, Confucius is critical of his disciple Shen Cheng 申棖 for possessing desire but not being firm. In his Collected Commentaries on the Analects [論語集注], Zhu Xi cites Cheng Yi 程頤 (1033–1107) as saying, “If a man has desire, he will be devoid of firmness, and if he is firm, he will not yield to desire.” The interpretation of this point given by Li Zehou 李澤厚 is redolent of Western philosophy. He believes that the “firmness” here refers to the construction of moral will.

    Moral will and its power display themselves in perceptual acts and practices, but their connotation lies in “rational cohesion,” that is, reason absolutely dominates and control sensibility (including desire). This is the foundation for moral reason. Whether it is said as categorical imperative which is external and transcendental or as “manifested intuitive knowledge (liangzhi 良知)” of the internal spirit, it is always characterized by this “firmness.”

    In fact, Lis is an over-interpretation, for this interpretation seems more applicable to Menciuss “pursuing goodness (shan 善),” but when concerned with Confucius, it goes too far.

    To Confucius, yu is not so strong in appeal to the power of moral will, and this is the very difference between him and Mencius in their theories of yu. Confuciuss “Is benevolence a thing remote? The moment I desire benevolence, benevolence is at hand” (7:30) is probably the core statement of his “desire for benevolence” (yu ren 欲仁). But here the yu itself is not clear in regard to its appeal to moral will for doing good and doing away with evil. His “desiring benevolence and securing it” (20:2), of course, implies knowing the good, and effort in pursuit of loving the good, but it does not possess the performative nature of doing good.

    When Confucius, says “Now the man of benevolence, desiring to be established himself, seeks also to establish others; desiring to be enlarged himself, he seeks also to enlarge others” (6:30), the connection between desire and benevolence lies at the core in that what the person of benevolence desires represents the realm of benevolence lofty and positive, and furthermore, both “desiring to be established himself” and “desiring to be enlarged himself” are for the sake of others. Confucius said only that “I have never seen one who loved virtue (de 德) as he loved beauty” (9:18, 15:13), which is a statement of an empirical fact, but not only did he never say that “l(fā)oving virtue is like loving beauty,” he also never said that “hating evil is like hating a stench.” The reason is that both loving virtue and hating evil stem from the power of moral will. Wang Yangming 王陽明 (1472–1529) understood intuitive knowledge first as meaning “the sense of right and wrong,” and then he furthered it to “the sense of likes and dislikes,” but this is an inheritance from Mencius.

    Menciuss Theory of Yu: ‘Who Commands Desire Is Good [86]

    According to the Index of the Mencius [孟子引得], in the Mencius, there are 95 places where the Chinese character yu 欲 is used. In light of modern desire theory, we find that Mencius is concerned about both subjective and objective desires. “I desire life, and I also desire righteousness (yi 義). If I cannot keep the two together, I will let life go, and choose righteousness.” (Mencius 6A:10) This means that the reason-providing desire which resorts to moral practice is more valuable than the reason-following desire for life.

    In a display of an avalanche-like moral momentum, Mencius expounds the two sides of life and death:

    I desire life indeed, but there is that which I desire more than life, and therefore, I will not seek to possess it by any improper ways. I dislike death indeed, but there is that which I dislike more than death, and therefore there are occasions when I will not avoid danger. If among the things which man desires there were nothing which he desired more than life, why should he not use every means by which he could preserve it? If among the things which man dislikes there were nothing which he disliked more than death, why should he not do everything by which he could avoid danger? There are cases when men by a certain course might preserve life, and they do not employ it; when by certain things they might avoid danger, and they will not do them. Therefore, men have that which they desire more than life, and that which they dislike more than death. They are not men of distinguished talents and virtue only who have this mental nature. All men have it; what belongs to such men is simply that they do not lose it. (Ibid.)

    Life is what people desire and death is what people dislike, but the power of moral emotion renders what people desire more desirable than life and what people dislike more undesirable than death. It is for this reason that a person of virtue never tries to turn to improper ways and avoid danger. To Mencius, this mind beyond life and death is not only owned by sages but should also be possessed by everyone. This indicates that it appeals to a moral universality.

    Nevertheless, Mencius, who pursued so high a moral level, does not deny simplistically such basic unmotivated desires of humankind as those for sensual pleasures. He says, “Mens mouths agree in having the same relishes; their ears agree in enjoying the same sounds; their eyes agree in recognizing the same beauty” (6A:7). Thus, with such low commonality of desires, he argues for the high commonality that everyone has morality, thus forming his manner of perceptual argumentation from the bottom up. In the entire text, Mencius tries to move readers by emotion (qing 情), and for this purpose he tends to resort to the perceptual power of morality. He always attempts to resolve the problems with yu by virtue. For example, consider this passage:

    The possession of beauty is what men desire, and Shun had for his wives the two daughters of Yao,i but this was not sufficient to remove his sorrow. Riches are what men desire, and the kingdom was the rich property of Shun, but this was not sufficient to remove his sorrow. Honors are what men desire, and Shun had the dignity of being sovereign, but this was not sufficient to remove his sorrow. The reason why being the object of mens delight and the possession of beauty, riches, and honors, were not sufficient to remove his sorrow was that it could be removed only by his getting his parents to be in accord with him. (5A:1)

    The essential point of Menciuss moral argumentation is his quietly replacing subjective desire with objective desire and turning reason-following desire to reason-providing desire, except that what is followed is instinctive reason and what is provided is moral reason. He makes that turn when he says, “To desire to be honored is the common mind of men. And all men have in themselves that which is truly honorable, only they do not think of it. The honor which men confer is not good honor” (6A:17). What on earth does his “good honor” mean? It requires moral sublimation as displayed by laying down ones life for righteousness, so that mens appeal to morality can be as natural as their satisfaction of their physiological desires.

    Owing to such a moral requirement, Mencius, indeed, shows a certain tendency to restrain desire (jie yu 節(jié)欲) but not to eradicate desire (jue yu 絕欲). “To nourish the mind, there is nothing better than to make the desires few. Here is a man whose desires are few—in some things he may not be able to keep his heart, but they will be few. Here is a man whose desires are many—in some things he may be able to keep his heart, but they will be few.” (7B:81) This indicates the dialectical relationship between the mind and yu in Menciuss sense. Even his remark, “l(fā)et a man not do what his own sense of righteousness tells him not to do, and let him not desire what his sense of righteousness tells him not to desire—to act thus is all he has to do” (7A:17), is often elevated by interpreters as acting against the mind. In Collected Commentaries on the Mencius [孟子集注], Zhu Xi cites Li Yu 李郁 (1086–1150) as saying,

    Not to do and desire something is what everyone has a mind to. However, when private intention stirs yet cannot be restrained with propriety and righteousness, there will be not a few who do what their own sense of righteousness tells them not to do and desire what their sense of righteousness tells them not to desire. If such mind can subdued, then in enlarging the mind for the sense of shame and dislike, righteousness can be inexhaustible. That is why Mencius says it and nothing more.

    In fact, the original intention of Mencius comes closer to meaning nothing more than that men shall not do what they should not do and not accept what they should not accept. And there is not necessarily a call for sublimating the mind in all cases.

    Unlike Confuciuss concern with the desire for benevolence, Menciuss main moral concern is the desire for goodness (yu shan 欲善). He believes that “a man who commands desire is what is called a good man” (7B:25). The “commanding desire” implies a very clear moral orientation, for inside it there must dwell the power of moral will which takes effect. First, knowing what is good and what is not good is the necessary condition for pursuing goodness. Second, turning from knowing to doing requires the impetus for doing goodness. Third, only with the ability to love goodness can the moral realm be elevated step by step. Mencius says,

    A man who commands his desire is what is called a good man. He whose goodness is part of himself is what is called a genuine man. He whose goodness has been filled up is what is called beautiful man. He whose completed goodness is brightly displayed is what is called a great man. When this great man exercises a transforming influence, he is what is called a sage. When the sage is beyond our knowledge, he is what is called a spirit-man. (7B:25)

    In this upward logical progress from goodness to realness, beautifulness, greatness, and sagehood to spirit, though the desire for goodness lies at the bottom, it serves as the most fundamental impetus, which can be traced back to the Four Beginnings (siduan 四端) of the mind expounded in the Mencius. In the Analects, there is also a collocation of desire and good: “In carrying on your government, why should you use killing at all? Let your evinced desires be for what is good, and the people will be good” (Analects 12:19). But here “desires” refers to specific good acts of avoiding killing, so it is quite conceptually different from Menciuss strong appeal to the will toward goodness.

    Therefore, the dominant use of yu in the text of the Mencius implies a strong inclination to goodness. This is true of either his saying “I desire to rectify mens minds” (Mencius 3B:9) or his dictum that “if a man can give full development to the mind which makes him shrink from intending to injure others, his benevolence will be more than can be called into practice” (7B:31). The reason for either is nothing but the desire for goodness.

    Xunzis Theory of Yu: ‘Human Desire Shared by All Alike [87]

    According to the Index of the Xunzi [荀子引得], the character yu 欲 appears in the Xunzi 236 times. This is a rather high number as far as pre-Qin classics go, but the concept of the character therein is much thinner. In the Xunzi, yu is not associated indirectly with benevolence, nor directly with goodness, but rather it has to do with evil and emotion. I once noted that, in contrast to evil which has only breadth but not depth, goodness has depth and diversity. Compared with Confuciuss yu and Menciuss yu, Xunzis yu is conceptually simpler and also enters necessarily into connection with human nature (xing 性), which needs the mind for its normative guidance.

    Let us first look at Xunzis logic from nature and emotion to yu. He says,

    Nature is a consequence of Heaven. Emotions are the substance of that nature. Desires are the resources of nature. Seeking what is desired is the response of the emotions. When what is desired is judged to be obtainable, it will be pursued. That is a necessary and inescapable part of our essential nature. Judging it possible and leading the way to it is where the intelligence must come into play. Thus, even though one was a mere gatekeeper, one could not get rid of his desires, for they are what nature possesses.

    After Menciuss saying that “to enjoy food and delight in colors is nature” (6A:4), this is also an early thought which affirms the existence and legitimacy of desire. However, Xunzi here does not, as claimed by his interpreters, treat desire as nature, for to link desire with nature requires the intermediate link of emotion, and in addition the mind functions to provide normative guidance to the progression of “nature–emotion–desire.” To put it from the opposite side, according to the developmental logic from desire to emotion and then to nature, it is what Xunzi sees as evil desire that carries with it evil emotion and then evil nature, but good mind causes “evil nature” to be altered. That is to say, desire enables human beings to undergo a transformation of nature and strive toward what is good. This is different from Menciuss “extending nature to the utmost and taking delight in doing what is good.” The difference between them is, at the same time, the very point where they can come into unity.

    Despite the conceptual thinness of Xunzis yu, his exposition of the objects involved in subjective desire is considerably rich. In “Contra Physiognomy” [非相], he affirms empirically the basic levels of humans yu like adequate or ample food and clothing as well as relaxation, believing them to be being inborn desires. On this basis, humans have various desires for both external and internal enjoyment.

    It is the essential nature of man that his eyes desire the most intense of colors, his ears the riches of sounds, his mouth the most intense of flavors, his nose the riches of aromas, and his mind the fullest relaxation and repose. Desiring these five limits of intensity is something the essential nature of man cannot escape. (Xunzi, “Of Kings and Hegemons” [王霸])

    Thus Xunzi connects desire and emotion directly. In addition, to him even the spiritual yu is also utilitarian. Being “fond of glory and sick of disgrace” (“Of Honor and Disgrace” [榮辱]), chasing fame and honor, hankering for power, and grabbing high positions are all objects of “fondness” for Xunzi.

    However, this inborn desire of humans can become the impetus for the origination of rites (li 禮) from the opposite side.

    How did rites arise? I say that men are born with desires which, if not satisfied, cannot but lead men to seek to satisfy them. If in seeking to satisfying their desires men observe no measure and apportion things without limits, then it would be impossible for them no to contend over the means to satisfy their desires. Such contention leads to disorder. Disorder leads to poverty. The ancient kings abhorred such disorder; so, they established the regulations contained within ritual and moral principles in order to apportion things, to nurture the desires of men, and to supply the means for their satisfaction. They so fashioned their regulations that desires should not want for the things which satisfy them and goods would not be exhausted by the desires. In this way the two of them, desires and goods, sustained each other over the course of time. This is the origination of rites. Thus, the meaning of rites is to nurture. (“Discourse on Rites” [禮論])

    Thus the interrelation between desires and materials is where rites arose, and thereby rites could regulate by nurturing. To Xunzi, the key to this process is progressing from desires to the Way (dao 道).

    The junzi enjoys obtaining proper instruction; the lesser men enjoy obtaining what they desire. When music is used to guide and regulate the desires, there is enjoyment but no disorder; when it is used for the desires with no thought of guidance, there is delusion but no enjoyment. (“Discourse on Music” [樂論])

    The Way, to sages, begins from the mind: “The sage follows his desires and fulfills his emotions, but having regulated them, he accords with rational principles of order. . . . This is the Way of putting the mind in order” (“Dispelling Blindness” [解蔽]).

    Therefore, to Xunzi, from mind to emotion and then to desire, an association forms so that mind regulates emotion and nurtures desire. “Order and disorder lie in what the mind permits and not with the desires that belong to our essential nature.” (“On the Correct Use of Names”) Though this is said from the angle of the consequentialism of governing a state, its key point lies in the distinction between the positive side of what the mind permits and the negative side of the overflowing desire for emotions. “That the occurrence of desire does not depend on its objects first being obtainable is a quality we receive from nature. That what we seek to satisfy our desires b following after what is possible is what we receive from the mind.” (Ibid.) What the mind in Xunzis sense possesses is mainly the rational connotation of consideration, which means that the perceptualization of the a priori desire demands its selection and governance by depending on the rationalization of the a posteriori mind.

    On the whole, Xunzis theory of yu belongs mainly to the subjective desires, that is to say, to the unmotivated desires with no calling for self-reflection, which follows common physiological and psychological desire. As regards this sort of emotion and desire with commonality, Xunzi says,

    To be as honored as the Son of Heaven and to be as wealthy by possessing the whole world—this natural human desire is shared by all alike. But if all men give free rein to their desires, the result would be impossible to endure and the material goods of the whole world would be inadequate to satisfy them. Accordingly, the Ancient Kings acted to control them with regulations, rites, and moral principles in order thereby to divide society into classes. (“Of Honor and Disgrace”)

    It is by means of rites that Xunzi regulates emotion and desire, rather than aiming for sublimation from the level of yu. By contrast, Mencius replaces objective desire from the inside with the subjective desire, transforming reason-following desire into reason-providing desire. This difference is concerned with the more fundamental difference between Menciuss approach of “thinking about nature in terms of mind” and Xunzis approach of “mind regulating nature and emotion.”

    Conclusion: The Emotion–Reason Structure Inherent?in Human Desire [88]

    By applying an approach informed by comparative philosophy and drawing on contemporary Western ethics, we have interpreted the theories of yu of Confucius, Mencius, and Xunzi in attempt to find a possible path through the jungle of early Confucian texts. Obviously, in Western ethics the dichotomies of subjective–objective, unmotivated–motivated, and reason-following and reason-providing desires are based on subject–object dualism, and in each of these dichotomies the two sides are split. However, such a split between desires does not exist in Confuciuss theory of yu at all, nor does it play a role in Mencius or Xunzi. Though Mencius always tries to turn subjective desire into objective desire, Xunzi focuses only on subjective desire, which he makes an internal specific differentiation. In my opinion, these dichotomies do nothing but describe the basic tendencies of human desires. In each of them, one type has to do with instinct, with no need of any reason, and the other is subject to moral sublimation. The former, naturally, is dominated by sensibility (though also involving potential reason), and the latter seems to be dominated by reason (though also imbued with emotion), thus forming an internal tension between emotion and reason. What the emotion–reason structure which Chinese thought contributes to the world aims for is the original integration and mutual penetration between the two sides.

    Confuciuss yu contains a connotation of subjective desire, but his “following what the mind desires” also displays implications of objective desire. Upon examination, we can say that his theory constitutes an integral structure of “desiring benevolence and securing it,” without calling for a clear choice between good and evil. Menciuss yu more often implies objective desire, for his intuitive knowledge and intuitive ability (liangneng 良能) resort to the moral will of desiring in order to do what is the good. Xunzis yu is basically subjective in connotation. Though the desires shared by all humans connect with evil, they can be refined by external transformation through rites and awareness of the minds capacity for good. Generally speaking, the yu that Mencius expounds is motivated desire, and it is the objective desire which should provide reason for moral actin in pursuit of goodness. The yu that Xunzi dwells on is unmotivated desire, and it is the subjective desire which causes the moral act toward evil and therefore is reason-following desire. Confucius falls between them, as his concept of yu, though not transcendentally attaining a realm free of good and evil, does not give a clear direction in regard to good and evil. Stemming from such plural possibilities are the Mencian and Xunzian tendencies toward good and evil desires: Menciuss top-down model of “good mind—good nature—good emotions” and Xunzis bottom-up model of “evil emotions—evil nature—good mind.”

    Early Confucian theories of yu reflected a Chinese wisdom paradigm with their own emotion–reason structure. This structure not only goes beyond the dualism of subjective and objective desires but also resolves the contradiction between emotionalism and rationalism as well, thus making it possible to return to the root and develop a new, integrated approach to such fundamental issues as human desire.

    Bibliography of Cited Translations

    Knoblock, John, trans. Xunzi [荀子] (Chinese–English version). 2 vols. Library of Chinese Classics [大中華文庫]. Changsha: Hunan Peoples Publishing House; Beijing: Foreign Languages Press, 1999.

    Legge, James, trans. Analects. http://ctext.org/analects, accessed August 15, 2021.

    ———. Mencius. https://ctext.org/mengzi, accessed August 15, 2021.

    Translated by Wang Xiaonong

    永久网站在线| 99热这里只有精品一区| 亚洲午夜理论影院| 日韩人妻高清精品专区| 深夜精品福利| 午夜福利视频1000在线观看| 日韩欧美国产在线观看| 中文亚洲av片在线观看爽| 日韩中字成人| 一夜夜www| 欧美色欧美亚洲另类二区| 国产在线精品亚洲第一网站| 国产精品98久久久久久宅男小说| 少妇被粗大猛烈的视频| 成人午夜高清在线视频| 免费黄网站久久成人精品| 伦精品一区二区三区| 欧美+亚洲+日韩+国产| 国产av不卡久久| 亚洲精华国产精华精| 91精品国产九色| 色5月婷婷丁香| 一进一出抽搐gif免费好疼| 精华霜和精华液先用哪个| 99九九线精品视频在线观看视频| 嫩草影院入口| 两人在一起打扑克的视频| 国产av一区在线观看免费| 午夜精品一区二区三区免费看| 伦理电影大哥的女人| 美女大奶头视频| 欧美性猛交╳xxx乱大交人| 日韩 亚洲 欧美在线| 欧美一级a爱片免费观看看| 亚洲成人精品中文字幕电影| 偷拍熟女少妇极品色| 51国产日韩欧美| 可以在线观看毛片的网站| 永久网站在线| 久久久久久久午夜电影| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区 | 日本欧美国产在线视频| 欧美潮喷喷水| av天堂在线播放| 丰满乱子伦码专区| 啦啦啦啦在线视频资源| 国产精品乱码一区二三区的特点| 久久精品国产自在天天线| 男女之事视频高清在线观看| 内地一区二区视频在线| 亚洲人成网站在线播放欧美日韩| 免费电影在线观看免费观看| 亚洲欧美日韩高清专用| 十八禁国产超污无遮挡网站| 身体一侧抽搐| 亚洲精品国产成人久久av| 国产成人aa在线观看| 窝窝影院91人妻| 欧美一区二区精品小视频在线| 久久精品影院6| 真人一进一出gif抽搐免费| 十八禁国产超污无遮挡网站| 国内少妇人妻偷人精品xxx网站| 国产欧美日韩精品亚洲av| 男人和女人高潮做爰伦理| 真实男女啪啪啪动态图| 精品一区二区三区人妻视频| 久久久久久大精品| 中出人妻视频一区二区| 变态另类成人亚洲欧美熟女| 国产精品自产拍在线观看55亚洲| 一级av片app| 特级一级黄色大片| 婷婷六月久久综合丁香| 99久久精品国产国产毛片| 又黄又爽又刺激的免费视频.| 在线天堂最新版资源| 在线免费观看的www视频| 午夜福利视频1000在线观看| 亚洲欧美日韩高清在线视频| 日韩精品青青久久久久久| 久久久久久大精品| 成熟少妇高潮喷水视频| 成人特级黄色片久久久久久久| 国产精品国产三级国产av玫瑰| 国产精华一区二区三区| 精品久久久噜噜| 1000部很黄的大片| 偷拍熟女少妇极品色| 又爽又黄无遮挡网站| 一个人看视频在线观看www免费| 亚洲自拍偷在线| 一个人免费在线观看电影| 国产精品伦人一区二区| h日本视频在线播放| 男女做爰动态图高潮gif福利片| 欧美黑人巨大hd| xxxwww97欧美| 亚洲色图av天堂| 精品一区二区免费观看| 18禁裸乳无遮挡免费网站照片| 99久久成人亚洲精品观看| 亚洲人成网站在线播放欧美日韩| 国产精品日韩av在线免费观看| 国产中年淑女户外野战色| 亚洲成av人片在线播放无| av中文乱码字幕在线| 少妇裸体淫交视频免费看高清| 蜜桃亚洲精品一区二区三区| 在线天堂最新版资源| 欧美激情在线99| 欧美另类亚洲清纯唯美| 午夜福利在线观看免费完整高清在 | 91久久精品国产一区二区成人| 国产69精品久久久久777片| 内射极品少妇av片p| 欧美日本亚洲视频在线播放| 午夜福利在线观看吧| 久久久久久久亚洲中文字幕| 成人av一区二区三区在线看| 亚洲av一区综合| 久久精品国产99精品国产亚洲性色| 黄色配什么色好看| 国产高清视频在线观看网站| 国产成人av教育| 国产精品亚洲美女久久久| 男女下面进入的视频免费午夜| 在线观看午夜福利视频| 99久久精品一区二区三区| 午夜免费成人在线视频| 两个人视频免费观看高清| 国产av一区在线观看免费| 亚洲一区二区三区色噜噜| 男女边吃奶边做爰视频| 99热这里只有精品一区| 欧美三级亚洲精品| 深爱激情五月婷婷| 欧美成人免费av一区二区三区| 国语自产精品视频在线第100页| 国产精品一及| 一级黄片播放器| 又黄又爽又免费观看的视频| 国产蜜桃级精品一区二区三区| 免费观看的影片在线观看| 99热精品在线国产| 精华霜和精华液先用哪个| 欧美成人一区二区免费高清观看| 十八禁国产超污无遮挡网站| 少妇人妻一区二区三区视频| 亚洲欧美清纯卡通| 国产亚洲精品综合一区在线观看| 3wmmmm亚洲av在线观看| 国产精品嫩草影院av在线观看 | 精品国产三级普通话版| 精品人妻熟女av久视频| 亚洲成av人片在线播放无| 日本-黄色视频高清免费观看| 国产国拍精品亚洲av在线观看| 亚洲欧美日韩卡通动漫| 99热这里只有精品一区| 嫩草影视91久久| 一级毛片久久久久久久久女| 亚洲天堂国产精品一区在线| 自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇| 99久久无色码亚洲精品果冻| 在线国产一区二区在线| avwww免费| 美女cb高潮喷水在线观看| 国产欧美日韩精品一区二区| 国产三级在线视频| 真人一进一出gif抽搐免费| 韩国av一区二区三区四区| 一a级毛片在线观看| 国产久久久一区二区三区| 国产伦一二天堂av在线观看| 欧美黑人欧美精品刺激| 老司机福利观看| 精品一区二区三区视频在线观看免费| 日本爱情动作片www.在线观看 | 在线观看66精品国产| 99在线人妻在线中文字幕| 99热这里只有是精品在线观看| 久久久久国产精品人妻aⅴ院| 色吧在线观看| 欧美色欧美亚洲另类二区| 成人永久免费在线观看视频| 亚洲18禁久久av| 三级毛片av免费| 黄色配什么色好看| 国产欧美日韩精品亚洲av| 成人二区视频| 99久久久亚洲精品蜜臀av| 美女xxoo啪啪120秒动态图| 如何舔出高潮| 中文字幕av成人在线电影| 欧美zozozo另类| 黄色欧美视频在线观看| 欧美bdsm另类| 麻豆成人午夜福利视频| 国产精品99久久久久久久久| 精品久久国产蜜桃| 亚洲天堂国产精品一区在线| 国产 一区精品| 久久久久九九精品影院| 欧美绝顶高潮抽搐喷水| 97超视频在线观看视频| 国产精品久久久久久久久免| av在线蜜桃| 国产黄色小视频在线观看| 老师上课跳d突然被开到最大视频| 999久久久精品免费观看国产| 欧美性感艳星| 中文字幕久久专区| 国产精品av视频在线免费观看| 好男人在线观看高清免费视频| 天天一区二区日本电影三级| 成人特级av手机在线观看| 欧洲精品卡2卡3卡4卡5卡区| 又粗又爽又猛毛片免费看| 男女视频在线观看网站免费| 伦精品一区二区三区| 深夜精品福利| 国产精品永久免费网站| 无遮挡黄片免费观看| 午夜福利视频1000在线观看| 网址你懂的国产日韩在线| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 欧美另类亚洲清纯唯美| 午夜福利18| 男人的好看免费观看在线视频| 亚洲无线观看免费| 九色成人免费人妻av| 精品日产1卡2卡| 人妻夜夜爽99麻豆av| 国产高清有码在线观看视频| 国产亚洲精品综合一区在线观看| 国产精品人妻久久久影院| 成人二区视频| 成人国产一区最新在线观看| 午夜福利视频1000在线观看| 一个人看的www免费观看视频| a级毛片免费高清观看在线播放| 日本三级黄在线观看| 中文字幕av成人在线电影| 一区二区三区免费毛片| 亚洲欧美日韩东京热| 欧美精品国产亚洲| 日韩欧美在线二视频| 22中文网久久字幕| 国产亚洲av嫩草精品影院| 不卡视频在线观看欧美| 久久久精品欧美日韩精品| 真实男女啪啪啪动态图| 男女做爰动态图高潮gif福利片| 亚洲欧美激情综合另类| 国产爱豆传媒在线观看| 久久午夜福利片| 人妻久久中文字幕网| 22中文网久久字幕| 好男人在线观看高清免费视频| 看十八女毛片水多多多| 国内毛片毛片毛片毛片毛片| 久久久久久久久中文| 国产精品久久久久久精品电影| 97超级碰碰碰精品色视频在线观看| 久久香蕉精品热| 日韩欧美免费精品| 国产探花在线观看一区二区| 国产91精品成人一区二区三区| 老司机午夜福利在线观看视频| 亚洲专区中文字幕在线| 麻豆成人午夜福利视频| 亚洲中文字幕一区二区三区有码在线看| а√天堂www在线а√下载| av专区在线播放| www.色视频.com| 最新在线观看一区二区三区| 久久精品人妻少妇| 国产精华一区二区三区| 国产毛片a区久久久久| 九九热线精品视视频播放| 十八禁国产超污无遮挡网站| 高清日韩中文字幕在线| 国产av一区在线观看免费| 亚洲自拍偷在线| 一进一出抽搐动态| 一区二区三区高清视频在线| 国产亚洲精品久久久com| 又黄又爽又免费观看的视频| 日本爱情动作片www.在线观看 | 国产三级中文精品| 国内精品宾馆在线| 欧美三级亚洲精品| 桃红色精品国产亚洲av| 国产视频一区二区在线看| а√天堂www在线а√下载| 色综合婷婷激情| 亚洲av美国av| 天堂影院成人在线观看| 黄色女人牲交| 蜜桃久久精品国产亚洲av| 村上凉子中文字幕在线| 午夜爱爱视频在线播放| 一区二区三区高清视频在线| 精品欧美国产一区二区三| 一个人看的www免费观看视频| 午夜亚洲福利在线播放| 日韩在线高清观看一区二区三区 | 级片在线观看| 久久久成人免费电影| 人妻久久中文字幕网| 亚洲美女黄片视频| 干丝袜人妻中文字幕| 亚洲av中文av极速乱 | 亚洲真实伦在线观看| 能在线免费观看的黄片| 久久热精品热| 51国产日韩欧美| 麻豆久久精品国产亚洲av| 中国美女看黄片| 少妇熟女aⅴ在线视频| 亚洲狠狠婷婷综合久久图片| netflix在线观看网站| 国国产精品蜜臀av免费| 成人精品一区二区免费| 十八禁网站免费在线| 高清在线国产一区| 色综合亚洲欧美另类图片| 91麻豆av在线| 日韩中字成人| 亚洲久久久久久中文字幕| 亚洲美女黄片视频| 国产单亲对白刺激| www日本黄色视频网| 麻豆精品久久久久久蜜桃| 成人毛片a级毛片在线播放| 亚洲va在线va天堂va国产| h日本视频在线播放| 久久6这里有精品| 国产伦一二天堂av在线观看| 观看美女的网站| 91狼人影院| 噜噜噜噜噜久久久久久91| 国产精品野战在线观看| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 亚洲三级黄色毛片| 色哟哟·www| 99精品在免费线老司机午夜| 床上黄色一级片| 淫妇啪啪啪对白视频| 国产91精品成人一区二区三区| 高清在线国产一区| 国产精品免费一区二区三区在线| 最近最新中文字幕大全电影3| 亚洲美女视频黄频| 成熟少妇高潮喷水视频| 波多野结衣高清无吗| 中亚洲国语对白在线视频| 免费人成在线观看视频色| 国产真实伦视频高清在线观看 | 精品一区二区免费观看| 老师上课跳d突然被开到最大视频| 国产蜜桃级精品一区二区三区| 欧美高清性xxxxhd video| 日韩精品有码人妻一区| 久久精品国产亚洲av天美| 国产高清激情床上av| 亚洲不卡免费看| 亚洲美女视频黄频| 国产又黄又爽又无遮挡在线| 亚洲一级一片aⅴ在线观看| 老师上课跳d突然被开到最大视频| 久久久久久伊人网av| 精品久久久久久成人av| 亚洲综合色惰| 成人美女网站在线观看视频| 国产一区二区在线av高清观看| 窝窝影院91人妻| 亚洲国产欧美人成| 欧美高清成人免费视频www| 欧美性猛交黑人性爽| 国产在线男女| 深爱激情五月婷婷| 成人高潮视频无遮挡免费网站| av视频在线观看入口| 国产毛片a区久久久久| 亚洲黑人精品在线| 免费av不卡在线播放| 亚洲精华国产精华精| 一级黄色大片毛片| 春色校园在线视频观看| av在线蜜桃| 午夜爱爱视频在线播放| 成人国产一区最新在线观看| 最新在线观看一区二区三区| 婷婷色综合大香蕉| 蜜桃久久精品国产亚洲av| 久久亚洲精品不卡| 久久国产精品人妻蜜桃| 国产av不卡久久| 国产精品野战在线观看| 美女xxoo啪啪120秒动态图| 国产免费男女视频| 女人十人毛片免费观看3o分钟| 老熟妇乱子伦视频在线观看| a在线观看视频网站| 国产午夜福利久久久久久| 久9热在线精品视频| 99久久久亚洲精品蜜臀av| 亚洲成人久久爱视频| 久久久午夜欧美精品| 99热这里只有是精品在线观看| 无遮挡黄片免费观看| 女的被弄到高潮叫床怎么办 | 精品久久久噜噜| 国产黄a三级三级三级人| 赤兔流量卡办理| 黄色视频,在线免费观看| 内射极品少妇av片p| 欧美在线一区亚洲| 国产老妇女一区| 成年人黄色毛片网站| 1000部很黄的大片| 欧美色欧美亚洲另类二区| 国产 一区精品| 精品久久久久久成人av| 97超视频在线观看视频| 国产在线男女| 日本a在线网址| 99久久九九国产精品国产免费| 夜夜爽天天搞| 日本-黄色视频高清免费观看| 简卡轻食公司| 欧美又色又爽又黄视频| 91精品国产九色| 草草在线视频免费看| 真实男女啪啪啪动态图| 欧美日韩中文字幕国产精品一区二区三区| 欧美+日韩+精品| 亚洲黑人精品在线| 国产一级毛片七仙女欲春2| 欧洲精品卡2卡3卡4卡5卡区| 草草在线视频免费看| 国产高清三级在线| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 亚洲无线观看免费| 嫩草影院入口| 亚洲成人久久性| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区 | 国产精品乱码一区二三区的特点| 中国美女看黄片| 三级国产精品欧美在线观看| x7x7x7水蜜桃| 少妇丰满av| 乱码一卡2卡4卡精品| 床上黄色一级片| 91狼人影院| 一个人观看的视频www高清免费观看| 在线观看免费视频日本深夜| 别揉我奶头~嗯~啊~动态视频| 国产av在哪里看| 亚洲avbb在线观看| 波多野结衣高清作品| 色综合婷婷激情| 成人午夜高清在线视频| 动漫黄色视频在线观看| 免费在线观看成人毛片| 成人国产麻豆网| 国产高清三级在线| 嫩草影院精品99| 亚洲国产精品合色在线| 嫁个100分男人电影在线观看| 一区二区三区高清视频在线| 男人狂女人下面高潮的视频| 一进一出好大好爽视频| 看片在线看免费视频| 免费看美女性在线毛片视频| 免费无遮挡裸体视频| 国产亚洲av嫩草精品影院| 亚洲精品亚洲一区二区| 精品99又大又爽又粗少妇毛片 | 久久久久免费精品人妻一区二区| 毛片一级片免费看久久久久 | 天天躁日日操中文字幕| 国内精品美女久久久久久| x7x7x7水蜜桃| 久久精品国产亚洲av香蕉五月| 日本一本二区三区精品| 俄罗斯特黄特色一大片| 亚洲专区国产一区二区| 99精品久久久久人妻精品| 日韩欧美精品v在线| 国产精品永久免费网站| 国国产精品蜜臀av免费| 国产精品一区二区三区四区免费观看 | 男女视频在线观看网站免费| 免费在线观看影片大全网站| 又爽又黄无遮挡网站| 亚洲av.av天堂| 国产av麻豆久久久久久久| 日本爱情动作片www.在线观看 | 亚洲自偷自拍三级| 亚洲无线观看免费| 18禁裸乳无遮挡免费网站照片| 又粗又爽又猛毛片免费看| 成人亚洲精品av一区二区| 88av欧美| 国产成人一区二区在线| 久久久久九九精品影院| 国产男靠女视频免费网站| 中文字幕免费在线视频6| 97超视频在线观看视频| 亚洲性久久影院| 成人无遮挡网站| 久久久久久九九精品二区国产| 极品教师在线视频| 久久人人爽人人爽人人片va| 不卡视频在线观看欧美| 在现免费观看毛片| 色在线成人网| 国产在视频线在精品| 淫秽高清视频在线观看| 在线观看66精品国产| 51国产日韩欧美| 久久亚洲精品不卡| 午夜视频国产福利| 男女视频在线观看网站免费| 国产乱人视频| 中文字幕免费在线视频6| 少妇的逼好多水| 又黄又爽又免费观看的视频| 99精品久久久久人妻精品| eeuss影院久久| 成人综合一区亚洲| 日本a在线网址| av在线蜜桃| 亚洲欧美精品综合久久99| 十八禁网站免费在线| 亚洲va日本ⅴa欧美va伊人久久| 成年人黄色毛片网站| 国产 一区精品| 国内精品久久久久精免费| а√天堂www在线а√下载| 精品一区二区三区人妻视频| 精品日产1卡2卡| 变态另类丝袜制服| 婷婷亚洲欧美| 无人区码免费观看不卡| 久久婷婷人人爽人人干人人爱| 看片在线看免费视频| 亚洲精华国产精华精| 日韩精品青青久久久久久| 黄色丝袜av网址大全| 乱人视频在线观看| 一区二区三区激情视频| 一级av片app| 国产欧美日韩精品亚洲av| 欧美激情久久久久久爽电影| 国产真实乱freesex| 精品国产三级普通话版| 午夜免费男女啪啪视频观看 | 国产淫片久久久久久久久| 午夜福利高清视频| 国产亚洲欧美98| 精品一区二区三区av网在线观看| 美女大奶头视频| 麻豆成人午夜福利视频| 999久久久精品免费观看国产| 可以在线观看的亚洲视频| 日本与韩国留学比较| 91精品国产九色| 久久精品国产亚洲av香蕉五月| 高清在线国产一区| 欧美黑人欧美精品刺激| 成人欧美大片| 乱人视频在线观看| 日韩,欧美,国产一区二区三区 | 久久国内精品自在自线图片| 国产高潮美女av| 亚洲人成伊人成综合网2020| 国产 一区精品| 色尼玛亚洲综合影院| 亚洲自偷自拍三级| 午夜免费男女啪啪视频观看 | 桃红色精品国产亚洲av| 日韩欧美 国产精品| 国产69精品久久久久777片| 日韩精品有码人妻一区| 国产高清三级在线| 色综合站精品国产| 免费看光身美女| 中国美女看黄片| 国产女主播在线喷水免费视频网站 | 国产亚洲av嫩草精品影院| 日本色播在线视频| 国产精品野战在线观看| 最后的刺客免费高清国语| 国产精品无大码| 国产av麻豆久久久久久久| 最后的刺客免费高清国语| 日本色播在线视频| 小蜜桃在线观看免费完整版高清| 久久久久国内视频| 精品人妻视频免费看| 国产精品野战在线观看| www.www免费av| 美女大奶头视频| 赤兔流量卡办理| 国产亚洲av嫩草精品影院| 午夜a级毛片| 色5月婷婷丁香| 国产精品一区www在线观看 | 18+在线观看网站| 国产精品嫩草影院av在线观看 | 中出人妻视频一区二区|