• <tr id="yyy80"></tr>
  • <sup id="yyy80"></sup>
  • <tfoot id="yyy80"><noscript id="yyy80"></noscript></tfoot>
  • 99热精品在线国产_美女午夜性视频免费_国产精品国产高清国产av_av欧美777_自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇_亚洲熟女精品中文字幕_www日本黄色视频网_国产精品野战在线观看 ?

    Ranges of Understanding:On the Vast Scope of Art Interpretation.A Wittgensteinian Perspective

    2018-06-17 07:58:04StefanMajetschak
    文藝理論研究 2018年1期

    Stefan Majetschak

    Abstract: The article examines the question ofwhat“understanding an artwork” means and offers some considerations about the ranges of understanding that we experience in interpretations of art: the vast scope between the contrasting extremes“expert knowledge” on the one hand and “artblindness” on the other.With respect to the philosophy of later LudwigWittgenstein itwill be shown what these ranges originate from and why they are unavoidable.Thismay come as a surprise to some philosophers since Wittgenstein usually is not regarded as someone from whom onemight expect pronouncements of an aesthetic nature.But in fact Wittgenstein had spent much time considering questions of art and art theory.Indeed in 1949 he even noted that besides“conceptual” questions only“aesthetic questions” could “really grip” him(CV 2006: 91e).However, he never formulated his reflections on questions of aesthetics in an extended and coherent series of remarks.Rather his observations in this regard are to be found in individual remarks scattered in considerable quantity throughout the papers of his Nachlass.In the paper at hand a certain number of them has been reconstructed systematically.

    Keywords: artworks; ranges of understanding; art blindness; expert knowledge

    It is a somewhat trivial observation thatworks of art, in particular works of visual art, about which I will speak in the first instance,exhibit semantic ranges in which they might be understood.In various epochs and in different cultures the same art object is often apprehended in quite different ways.In borderline cases,itmay happen within the same epoch and culture that what appears to some as an art work worthy of aesthetic admiration is regarded by others as an objectnot to be taken seriously,as is crystal clear from the interminable debates still being conducted about works of art such as Marcel Duchamp's“Fountain” of1917.Buteven ifwe take the example of a Picasso painting,whose ontological status as an “artwork” is scarcely in dispute, it is clear that what people see and understand can be extremely varied.For its understanding can clearly range from well-informed expert knowledge to irredeemably ignorant art blindness.

    In the following remarks Iwish to examine the question of what“understanding art works” really means and to say a little of the ranges of understanding between the contrasting extremes“expert knowledge” on the one hand and “art blindness” on the other.In this regard, Iwould like to offer an explanation ofwhat these ranges originate from and why they are unavoidable.Iwill do this—which may perhaps come as a surprise to some readers—with respect to considerations of the philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein,who is generally regarded as an analytical philosopher of language,but not as someone from whom one might expect pronouncements of an aesthetic nature.But in fact Wittgenstein had spent his whole life considering questions of art and art theory.Indeed in 1949 he even noted that besides“conceptual” questions only“aesthetic questions” could “really grip” him(CV 2006: 91e).However, he never formulated his reflections on questions of aesthetics in an extended and coherent series of remarks.Rather his observations in this regard are to be found in individual remarks scattered in considerable quantity throughout the papers of his Nachlass,which we have to reconstruct.

    Although I will make use of his thoughts primarily to explain the concept of“understanding”with respect to works of the visual arts,his own examples usually come from music,the art form most immediately familiar to him.Music is thus principally what he refers to when he thinks about what“understanding” of an artwork means.In a long remark made in 1948 with the title“Understanding&Explaining a musical phrase”(CV 2006: 79e), he was therefore concerned to point outwith respect tomusic thatwhatwe call the“understanding” of an artwork is neither something like a mental process that accompanies its external perception nor a“specific experiential content” (CV 2006:80e)which we gain from perceiving it.Wittgenstein knows, of course, that we are often tempted to explain the understanding of art in this way.But whatever may happen internally in a person who perceives an art work:these mental processes and contents within a person at least cannot be what causes us to attribute or deny to someone artistic judgement,since usually we know nothing at all about them when we do so.And this shows that criteria other than internal processes or contents must govern our utterances when we talk about somebody's“understanding” of art: criteria like perceivable phenomena of expression in a person's behaviour,his or her acting or speaking and so on.For, to remain with this example,

    [a]ppreciation of music is expressed in a certain way,both in the course of hearing&playing and at other times too.This expression sometimes includes movements,but sometimes only the way the one who understands plays, or hums,occasionally too paralles he draws&images which, as it were, illustrate the music.Someone who understands music will listen differently(with a different facial expression, e.g.), play differently,hum differently,talk differently about the piece than someone who does not understand.(CV 2006:80e)

    Das Verst?ndnis der Musik hat einen gewissen Ausdruck, sowohl w?hrend des H?rens und Spielens, als auch zu andern Zeiten.Zu diesem Ausdruck geh?ren manchmal Bewegungen,manchmal aber nur, wie der Verstehende das Stück spielt,oder summt, auch hie&da Vergleiche,die er zieht, &Vorstellungen, die die Musik gleichsam illustrieren.Wer Musik versteht,wird anders(mit anderem Gesichtsausdruck, z.B.)zuh?ren, anders spielen, anders summen, andersüber das Stück reden, als der es nicht versteht.(CV 2006:80)

    In particular,experts who demonstrate their understanding not only behave in theway described,but also speak in a certain way,and so consideration of what is really said by them in aesthetic explanations may be helpful when it comes to specifying precisely what ismeant by understanding music or understanding art in general.

    So,what is really being said in aesthetic explanations of experts?In his Cambridge lectures on aesthetics from 1938Wittgenstein made an important observation in this regard:he pointed out that experts, when they “ make an aesthetic judgement about a thing, [...] do not just gape at it and say: ‘Oh, how marvellous!’” (L&V 1966:6).Rather they usually make much more complex statements.“A person who has a judgement” in aesthetic matters, therefore, “doesn’ t mean a person who says‘Marvellous’ at certain things”(ibid.).On the contrary, “it is remarkable”,Wittgenstein emphazised, “that adjectives such as‘beautiful’, ‘fine’” or‘marvellous’ “play hardly any role” (V&L 1966: 3)when talking about arts knowledgeably. “Words such as ‘lovely’”,‘marvellous’ oder‘beautiful’, according to Wittgenstein's shrewd observation, mostly“are first used as interjections”, particularly by“people[...] who can’ t express themselves properly”(ibid.)with respect to arts because they lack the ability to make a differentiated and appropriate judgement about an art work.The expert,on the other hand,is someone able to make competent judgements inmatters of art—and it is precisely in this field thatwe“distinguish between a person who knows what he is talking about and a person who doesn’t” (L&V 1966: 6).He does not simply say‘marvellous’ or‘lovely’, but rather gives reasons for his aesthetic judgements by talking in a certain way.

    An expert will justify his aesthetic judgement that a particular art work is original, inspiring,interesting or whatever else, for example, by pointing out how the work of art in question can or should be looked at.Thismeans:he will emphasize aspects of the art work respectively the art work's internal structure that deserve particular consideration, and so on.And for this reason,according to Wittgenstein, in “conversations on aestheticmatters” use is frequentlymade of“words”such as:

    “‘You have to see it like this, this is how it ismeant’; ‘When you see it like this, you see where it goeswrong’; ‘You have to hear these bars as an introduction”; “You must listen out for this key’; ‘You must phrase it like this’”

    “‘Du musst es so sehen, so ist es gemeint’;, Wenn Du es so siehst, siehst Du, wo der Fehler liegt’; ‘Du musst diese Takte als Einleitung h?ren’;, Du musst nach dieser Tonart hinh?ren’; ‘Du musst es so phrasieren’”

    and so on.Bymeans of formulations like these the expert draws attention to the possibility of noticing a particular aspect in an art work,in the light of which its structure or contentmight become intelligible to the listener or observer.Therefore one can-as Joachim Schulte has already emphasized-say in a certain respect that‘understanding an artwork’means forWittgenstein“something like seeing a new aspect of an object”, which changes our previous understanding of the artwork in question.When we notice a certain aspect,i.e.the fact that something can be seen or heard as something,we thus do not only see differently,but also see the work quite different,i.e.in a way in which we did not perceive it before.

    This noticing of aspects—the seeing or perceiving of something as something—was examined elaborately byWittgenstein in hisMS 144,themanuscript that served as the basis of what was formerly known as Part 2 of Philosophical Investigations.When he addresses the issue of‘seeing as’ here, he does not refer explicitly to art examples, butwhen he asks himself elsewhere:“how do we arrive at the concept‘seeing this as that’ at all?On what occassions does it get formed,when is there need of it?” He answers:“Very frequently in art” (Z 1967: 208).The fact that in music a sequence of tones can be heard as an introduction,in a poem a verse can be perceived as amelody or in a painting a figure can be seen as a portrait of the donor:“Those are the things that are often noticed by experts”, as Schulte rightly comments.

    In MS 144Wittgenstein discussed what he calls“noticing an aspect” (PI 2009: 203)or the“l(fā)ighting up” (PI 2009: 204)of an aspect, as already stated,not using examples of art but by means of a series of simple figures,including a drawing from Joseph Jastrow's Fact and Fable in Psychology(1901),which can be seen as the head of a duck or a rabbit.It achieved a certain celebrity under the name“the duck-rabbit”(ibid.).But even in this trivial example it is possible to illustrate what the expert does when explaining that certain aspects can be noticed in works of art.

    To be clear about what it means to notice an aspect in this duck-rabbit drawing, it is, according toWittgenstein, “useful to introduce the concept of a picture-object”(PI 2009: 204)into the discussion and to differentiate between it and the pictorial inscription at hand.The picture-object is what a viewer sees in a pictorial inscription and normally, that is, in the case of images whose type of representation is familiar to us,the identification of the picture-object is in no way variable in interpretation and aspect-related but clear-cut.

    So,with regard to what is visible to us, for example, in the greyscale proportions of black and white photography, we do not say:‘I see this as Ludwig Wittgenstein.’Rather we say: ‘I see Wittgenstein’ or‘I see Wittgenstein on the photograph.’The clear-cut nature of the identification thus depends not somuch on the objective qualities of the inscription confronting us butmore on whether we are familiar with the representational type of the image,for example a particular style of painting or,in this case,the photographic greyscale proportions and whether we know how to read them.AsWittgenstein asks:

    “‘Could Isay whata picturemustbe like to produce this effect[i.e.a clearcut identification of the picture-object/S.M.]?No.There are, for example, styles of painting which do not convey anything to me in this immediate way,but do to other people.I think that custom and upbringing have a hand in this.”(PI 2009:211)

    “K?nnte ich sagen, wie ein Bild beschaffen sein muss, um dies[ sc.Eindeutigkeit der Identifikation/S.M.]zu bewirken?Nein.Es gibt Malweisen,die mir nichts in dieser unmittelbaren Weise mitteilen,aber doch andern Menschen.Ich glaube,dass Gewohnheit und Erziehung hier mitzureden haben.(PI 2009:211)

    The painting styles that we have learned and see applied, for example, also in the duck-rabbit,are indeed not“arbitrary” for us, in the sense of being randomly exchangeable,for we cannot simply“choose one at pleasure[...] (The Egyptian, for instance.)” (PI 2009: 241).But, depending on custom and upbringing,they are conventional.For even in the case of images that use representational styles that we regard as quite“naturalistic”, e.g.photographs,we can still imagine that they say nothing to people who have grown up and live in another cultural context and allow them no clear-cut identification of the picture-object they are looking at.“[W]e view the photograph, the picture on our wall, as the very object(the man, landscape, and so on)represented in it” (PI 2009: 216).However,this

    “need not have been so.We could easily imagine people who did not have this attitude to such pictures.Who,for example,would be repelled by photographs,because a face without colour,and even perhaps a face reduced in scale, struck them as inhuman.”(ibid.)

    “müsste nicht sein.Wir k?nnen uns leicht Menschen vorstellen,die zu diesen Bildern nicht dies Verh?ltnis h?tten.Menschen z.B.,die von Photographien abgesto?en würden, weil ihnen ein Gesicht ohne Farbe,ja vielleicht ein Gesicht in verkleinertem Ma?stab,unmenschlich vork?me.” (PI2009: 216)

    Nevertheless,we will never say when looking at a photograph:“I see or interpret this as Wittgenstein.” Instead, we say:“Isee Wittgenstein.”

    In the case of the duck-rabbit the situation is the exact opposite:in this simple figure a painting style familiar to us,that is the convention of representing a form by means of outlines,is used in such a way that the inscription can be read multiaspectually and, to this extent, two different pictureobjects can be identified.One might say that this,in a certain sense,is the point of this primitive image.Of the one who fails to see this and accordingly only sees a“picture-rabbit” (PI 2009:204),it will probably be said that he does not understand the image because he fails to see an aspect that can be noticed.And so one will perhaps try to help him to understand by saying things such as, “Youmust see the image as a duck” or perhaps“You must see the left side of the image as a duck's beak.Then you'll understand it.”O(jiān)ne will thus draw attention to the noticeable aspects.This may draw the viewer's attention to the possible aspect change that has been created in the image and enable him to see that the inscription permits multiple readings.When this is the case,he understands the inscription differently,and perhaps he will say, “Now Isee it as a duck” or express his new understanding bymeans of a formulation such as“That is a tilting image that can be seen as a rabbit and as a duck.”

    In the case of the duck-rabbit,noticing the different aspects can be called “understanding” and pointing to them by means of sentences like“You have to see this as that” “explaining” the picture.And perhaps to the surprise ofmany,this thoroughly can be compared to what is called understanding and explaining in fine arts.Indeed,inasmuch as Wittgenstein's observation that the concept“seeing this as that”has its rightful place in an art context is correct, one can probably even say that, using the duck-rabbit as an example, we have, as it were,played through what it means to“understand and explain”a work of art.For precisely in art contexts an expert will usually try to make aspects of an art work noticeable with his explanations,pointing out how something in the art work can be seen as something.And in this way he will try to open up“understanding”.

    To relate this claim more closely to the practice ofmaking aesthetic judgements,let us take as an example Picasso's Le Rêve(The Dream)painted in 1932.The painting uses the late Cubist style that we,accustomed to the many different styles of representation that have developed in the course of about 150 years of western modern art,are not likely to reject as unintelligible or disfigured.Rather,it allows us to clearly identify the picture-object of the image.We see a woman sitting in an armchair,head to one side, dreaming, from which the painting gets its name.And there are viewers who perceive nothing other than this in the painting.However,one can become aware of the fact that Picasso,when painting the face of the woman,also made use of the phenomenon of“shape change or aspect change”which we know from the duck-rabbit drawing.When an expert, in this case an art historian, points this out to us, we notice perhaps all of a sudden:“The dreaming eye of the woman can be seen not only as an eye, butalso as the sexual organ of aman.” The interpretation of the expert emphasizes this aspect and, thanks to the explanation, we will possibly understand the painting in a different way.We will then, like the expert, perhaps say that Picasso's multi-aspectual fusion of eye and male sexual organ in the pictorial arrangement of the face of the dreaming woman goes plausibly“beyond the apparently unconnected,joins together the heterogeneous and thereby provocatively makes something visible, that is unique, that has never been seen like this before”.But whatever we then say: If we notice here the possible aspect, we will probably understand the painting in a different way and are likely to interpret it differently,for example with regard to the question of what the woman is dreaming.

    Both the duck-rabbit and Picasso's painting are examples that seem to confirm the remark of Joachim Schulte cited earlier that understanding an artwork is something like seeing a new aspect of the object at hand.For,to the extent that the inscriptions in both casesmight from the start have been created in order to generate amultiplicity of readings,these readings can be regarded as based on properties of the inscriptions as such.And so it is not implausible to speak of“understanding” as noticing an aspect of the art work itself.But unfortunately,the matter is much more complicated in many,probably most works of art.When we point to an aspectwith regard to its visual or auditive presence and say, “You have to hear this sequence of tones as an introduction” or“You must see this figure as a variation of an old iconographic motif”and thereby open up new ranges of understanding and interpretation,we do not refer to an objective property of the object itself.Rather,one has to realize, as Wittgenstein puts it, that“ what I perceive in the lighting up of an aspect is not a property of the object,but an internal relation between it and other objects” (PI 2009: 223).

    Strictly speaking,whatWittgenstein emphasizes in this passage is also true in the case of the duckrabbit and of Picasso's painting.When we notice that the duck-rabbit, among other things, can be seen as a duck or the upper half of the woman's face in Picasso's painting as a male sexual organ,we perceive an internal relation between the pictureobject and other objects familiar to us from other contexts.It strikes us,and this draws our attention to something new that is not, like a property,already founded in the picture-object itself.The same is true,with reference to Wittgenstein's favourite repertoire of examples,of noticing an aspect in music,e.g.when we learn to understand a sequence of tones as an ecclesiastical mode of church music.

    “To understand an ecclesiastical mode doesn’t mean to get used to a sequence of tones[...].It means,rather, to hear something new, something that I haven’t heard before, say like—indeed quite analogously to—suddenly being able to see 10 lines,which earlier Iwas only able to see as 2 times 5 lines,as a characteristic whole.” (BT 2013: 442 [322])

    “Eine Kirchentonart verstehen, hei?t nicht, sich an die Tonfolge gew?hnen[...].Sondern es hei?t, etwas Neues h?ren, was ich früher noch nicht geh?rt habe,etwa in der Art— ja ganz analog—, wie esw?re, 10 Striche, die ich früher nur als 2 mal 5 Striche habe sehen k?nnen, pl?tzlich als ein charakteristisches Ganzes sehen zu k?nnen.” (BT 2013: 442 [322])

    It is, of course, right that different inscriptions in painting and drawing or different tone sequences in music motivate aspect perception in varying degrees.Therefore,one would have to distinguish between images such as the duck-rabbit and Picasso's painting,which are both created from the outset to allow several aspects to emerge and art workswhich correlate to other objects in an internal relation only because the interpreter places the work into an appropriate,but hitherto unconsidered context of comparison.But Wittgenstein was not interested in this difference.His concern was the basic insight that no audible or visible sequence of inscriptions in a certain medium(words in a poem,brush strokes in painting,tones in music or whatever),compels us to notice an internal relation between it and something elsemerely because of its objective properties.Rather,that some internal relation between an art work and other objects becomes audible or visible always depends on the contextualizations with which we surround the given signs.Wittgenstein shows this using quite simple examples:

    One could imagine the illustration

    appearing in several places in a book,a textbook for instance.In the accompanying text,something different is in question every time:here a glass cube, there an upturned open box, there a wire frame of that shape,there three boards forming a solid angle.Each time the text supplies the interpretation of the illustration.(PI 2009:203)

    Man k?nnte sich denken,dass an mehreren Stellen eines Buches,z.B.eine Lehrbuches,die Illustration

    stünde.Im dazugeh?rigen Text ist jedesmal von etwas anderem die Rede:Einmal von einem Glaswürfel, einmal von einer umgestülpten offenen Kiste, einmal von einem Drahtgestell,das diese Form hat, einmal von drei Brettern, die ein Raumeck bilden.Der Text deutet jedesmal die Illustration.(PI 2009:203)

    According to the context, we can “see the illustration now as one thing, now as another” (PI 2009: 203).Very often these contextualizations,asWittgenstein says, may simply be“fictions”.He demonstrates this once again by means of a simple sign.

    And what is true of this simple sign is,of course,particularly true of artworkswith their often complex internal structure,which can motivate a large number of contextualizations.

    Precisely for this reason,with regard to works of art those vast scopes of understanding open up.Theymove between the extremes of expert knowledge on the one hand and art blindness on the other.The one who is blind to art—and Iwill return to this soon— is the one who,when looking at an art work,is unable to see any internal relation between the object and other objects because no appropriate contextualization occurs to him.He is able to see,for example,in Duchamp's Fountain nothing more than an object of everyday use.By contrast,individuals we call experts are able,by means of appropriate contextualizations,to allow internal relations between the work at hand and other objects to emerge and so to make aspects visible in the light ofwhich the work can be understood.With regard to art works such contextualizations,as Wittgenstein saw, will often be‘fictions’, which require on the part of the expert“imagination” (PI 2009:218),for they must occur to him as appropriate contextualizations that make aspects accessible and thus open up understanding.This does, of course,notmean that the contexts that we allow to occur to us and in which a work of art can be acceptably placed can be invented totally at random.On the contrary,it belongs to the skills required for an expert in aesthetic judgements that he is able to plausibly anchor an art work in the context of our culture-specific art forms and art historical traditions.

    The expertwho does this will then undoubtedly offer us, in order to make a work intelligible,“certain comparisons-grouping together of certain cases” (L&V 1966: 29).In Wittgenstein's opinion such comparisons arewhat“we reallywant” in order“to solve aesthetic puzzles” (ibid.)presented to us by many works.Thus, the expert will say, as we have seen in the example of Picasso's painting,something like, “You have to see this as that”, and so on.Or, he will“sometimes find the similarity between the style of a musician and the style of a poet who lived at the same time, or a painter”(L&V 1966:32)since— asWittgenstein put it in 1948— “teaching” someone“to appreciate poetry or painting can be part of an explanation of what music is” (CV 2006: 81e).In any case he will try to create,by means of offering a suitable contextualization,a new internal relation between the inner structure of the work and that what the work in his opinion refers to or expresses.

    “Take Brahms and Keller”, Wittgenstein is supposed to have said in his 1938 lectures:

    I often found that certain themes of Brahms were extremely Kellerian.This was extraordinarily striking[…]If I say this theme of Brahms is extremely Kellerian,the interest this has is first that these two lived at the same time.Also that you can say the same sortof things on both of them—the culture of the time in which they lived.If I say this,this comes to an objective interest.The interest might be that my words suggest a hidden connection.(L&V 1966: 32)

    This“hidden connection” might not have been noticed before.Only by grouping the two in thisway an internal relation becomes evident which sheds new light on both.Thus like in a“surveyable representation” — Wittgenstein's primary means of presenting material in philosophy—a specific grouping of the facts“points to a secret law” (GB 1979:8)within a realm of philosophical problems,a particular comparison between art forms or specific artworks of a time can help making visible hitherto unnoticed internal relations.

    More important than reflecting on the means,however,thatmight serve to open up internal relations are the philosophical consequences connected with his insights.Because everything that the expert will say is ultimately bound up with his being able to surround the work with the appropriate“fiction”,aesthetic explanations, according to Wittgenstein,are based fundamentally on nothing else than acceptance.This means: “ You have to give the explanation that is accepted.This is the whole point of the explanation” (L&V 1966: 18).Since the aspect to which it points is not an objective property of the object,it is impossible to prove its correctness bymeans of criteria that we normally use to justify empirical statements.That iswhy he towhom Ioffer such an aesthetic explanation,for instance with regard to a passage in a piece ofmusic,does

    not have to accept the explanation;it is not after all as though I had given him compelling reasons for comparing this passage with this&that.In did not e.g.explain to him that remarks made by the composer show that this passage is supposed to represent this&that.(CV 2006:79e)

    musste er ja die Erkl?rung nicht annehmen; es ist ja nicht, als h?tte ich ihm sozusagen überzeugende Gründe dafür gegeben,dass diese Stelle vergleichbar ist dem&dem.Ich erkl?re ihm ja, z.B.,nicht aus?u?erungen des Komponisten,diese Stelle habe das&das darzustellen.(CV 2006:79)

    Of course,it is true that certain patterns of explanation,certain ways of enveloping works of art with ‘fictions’ are more convincing at certain times than at others.“At a given time the attraction of a certain kind of explanation is greater than you can conceive” (L&V 1966: 24).When Wittgenstein held his lectures about aesthetics at the end of the 1930s,psychoanalytical patterns of explanation were extraordinarily common,and he discusses them critically and in detail in his lectures.Intertextual and interpictorial patterns of explanation,which see texts and images become visible in other texts and images,clearly appeal to art study and criticism today.But whether this or any other type of explanation makes the work understandable for anyone is in principle an open question.

    And itmust remain an open question since,as Wittgenstein asks, couldn’t“there be human beings lacking the ability to see something as something—and what what would that be like?” (PI 2009:224).The term he uses of this“defect” is“aspect-blindness” (ibid.).People being aspectblind would principally be unable to understand an explanation encouraging them to see something as something.Probably nobody has this defect in a fullscale radical form.But,if one accepts Wittgenstein's suggestion that“[a]spect-blindness will be akin to the lack of a‘musical ear’” (PI 2009:225)and analogously regards art blindness as a less dangerous kind of aspect-blindness,one has to admit that art blindness as the inability to imagine an internal relation between the artwork and other objects is really quite common among people and, where this defect is present, at least every form of aesthetic explanation is doomed to failure.

    Notes

    ①The writings of Ludwig Wittgenstein are cited here using the uniform citation keys,which can be found in the Bibliographie der deutsch-und englischsprachigen Wittgenstein-Ausgaben/Bibliography of German and English Editions of Wittgenstein(published in Wittgenstein-Studien 02/2011,249-286),compiled by Alois Pichler and Michael Biggs.This bibliography can also be downloaded as a PDF file at www.ilwg.eu.

    ②The case in which we maintain of ourselves that we understand a work of artmay, for the sake of simplicity, be excluded here.When we say:“Now Iunderstand themusic!”(or the poem, the picture etc), we identify our understanding of course not with the help of criteria of any sort.

    ③ Three students, Rush Rhees, Yorick Smithies and James Taylor,attended these lectures and took notes which have been published as Lectures and Conversations on Aethetics,Psychology and Religious Belief.Edited by Cyril Barrett,Oxford:Basil Blackwell1966(cited as L&C 1966).

    ④ MS 144,i.e.the formerly so-called second part of the Philosophical Investigations,is included in PI2009 under the title Philosophie der Psychologie—Ein Fragment/Philosophy of Psychology—A Fragment and cited hereinafter with the page number of PI2009.The passage quoted above is from PI 2009:213.

    ⑤ Joachim Schulte, “?sthetisch richtig“, in: Joachim Schulte, Chor und Gesetz.Wittgenstein im Kontext,F(xiàn)rankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp 1990,84.My translation.

    ⑥See note 5.

    ⑦ In German:“H-E-Kopf” (PI2009: 204).

    ⑧ In German:“Bildgegenstand” (PI 2009: 204).

    ⑨ Axel Müller, “Syntax ohne Worte.Das Kunstwerk als Beziehungsform “, in: Klaus Sachs-Hombach/Klaus Rehk?mper(Hrsg.), Bildgrammatik.Interdisziplin?re Forschungen zur Syntax bildlicher Darstellungsformen,Magdeburg: Scriptum 1999,236.My translation.

    ⑩In the passage cited the German text uses the word“Vorstellungskraft” (PI 2009: 218).In what follows Wittgenstein also mentions“Phantasie” (PI 2009: 224),which in the English version is also translated as‘imagination’.

    [11] For a more detailed interpretation of Wittgenstein's comparison between the music of Johannes Brahms and the writing of Gottfried Keller see Joachim Schulte, “WhatMakes Brahms Kellerian?”, in: Stefan Majetschak, Anja Weiberg(Eds.),Aestheticts Today.Contemporary Approaches to the Aesthetis of Nature and of Art, Berlin/Boston: De Gruyter 2017.

    [12] See on this pointmore detailed Stefan Majetschak, Survey and Surveyability.Remarks on two central notions in Wittgenstein's later philosophy, in: Wittgenstein-Studien 07(2016).

    Works Cited

    Barrett, Cyril, ed.Lectures and Conversations on Aethetics,Psychology and Religious Belief.Ed.Cyril Barrett.Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1966(cited as L&C 1966).

    Majetschak,Stefan.“Survey and Surveyability.Remarks on two central notions in Wittgenstein's later philosophy.”in: Wittgenstein-Studien 7(2016):65- 80.

    Müller, Axel.“Syntax ohne Worte.Das Kunstwerk als Beziehungsform.” in: Klaus Sachs-Hombach/Klaus Rehk?mper(Hrsg.), Bildgrammatik.Interdisziplin?re Forschungen zur Syntax bildlicher Darstellungsformen.Magdeburg:Scriptum 1999.

    Pichler, Alois, and Michael Biggs, eds.Bibliographie der deutsch-und englischsprachigen Wittgenstein-Ausgaben/Bibliography of German and English Editions of Wittgenstein.In: Wittgenstein-Studien 2(2011):249-86.

    Schulte, Joachim. “ ?sthetisch richtig.” in: Joachim Schulte:Chor und Gesetz.Wittgenstein im Kontext.Frankfurt/Main:Suhrkamp 1990.

    ---.“What Makes Brahms Kellerian?.” in: Aestheticts Today:Contemporary Approaches to the Aesthetis of Nature and of Art.Eds.Stefan Majetschak and Anja Weiberg.Berlin/Boston: De Gruyter, 2017.

    日日摸夜夜添夜夜添小说| 女警被强在线播放| 99国产极品粉嫩在线观看| 看黄色毛片网站| 日本一区二区免费在线视频| 中文字幕熟女人妻在线| 亚洲乱码一区二区免费版| 久久久久免费精品人妻一区二区| 99久久国产精品久久久| 亚洲av日韩精品久久久久久密| 妹子高潮喷水视频| 国产精品乱码一区二三区的特点| 亚洲av片天天在线观看| 嫩草影院精品99| 久久婷婷成人综合色麻豆| 九色国产91popny在线| 国产精品 欧美亚洲| av超薄肉色丝袜交足视频| 亚洲成人久久性| 人人妻人人看人人澡| 国模一区二区三区四区视频 | av有码第一页| 桃色一区二区三区在线观看| 美女黄网站色视频| 亚洲 欧美一区二区三区| 亚洲,欧美精品.| 国产精品亚洲一级av第二区| 免费一级毛片在线播放高清视频| 亚洲欧美精品综合久久99| 黄频高清免费视频| 午夜两性在线视频| 很黄的视频免费| 国产免费av片在线观看野外av| 不卡一级毛片| 99热这里只有是精品50| 校园春色视频在线观看| 午夜亚洲福利在线播放| 国产野战对白在线观看| 99国产精品一区二区三区| 国产成人精品无人区| 黄片小视频在线播放| 2021天堂中文幕一二区在线观| 国产亚洲精品久久久久久毛片| 免费人成视频x8x8入口观看| 黄色成人免费大全| 国产亚洲av嫩草精品影院| 国产精品免费一区二区三区在线| 久久精品人妻少妇| 特大巨黑吊av在线直播| 女生性感内裤真人,穿戴方法视频| 免费在线观看日本一区| 欧美人与性动交α欧美精品济南到| 老汉色av国产亚洲站长工具| 亚洲av成人一区二区三| 国产日本99.免费观看| 亚洲五月天丁香| 国产欧美日韩一区二区三| 国产精品国产高清国产av| 欧美丝袜亚洲另类 | 首页视频小说图片口味搜索| 18禁裸乳无遮挡免费网站照片| 国产精品影院久久| 亚洲中文日韩欧美视频| 桃色一区二区三区在线观看| 亚洲色图 男人天堂 中文字幕| 亚洲精华国产精华精| 两个人免费观看高清视频| 国产成人精品久久二区二区免费| 国内久久婷婷六月综合欲色啪| 日韩有码中文字幕| 中文字幕人成人乱码亚洲影| 亚洲天堂国产精品一区在线| 欧美人与性动交α欧美精品济南到| 亚洲aⅴ乱码一区二区在线播放 | 老熟妇仑乱视频hdxx| 日韩欧美国产在线观看| 母亲3免费完整高清在线观看| 日韩精品免费视频一区二区三区| 中文亚洲av片在线观看爽| 欧美乱色亚洲激情| 国产aⅴ精品一区二区三区波| 免费看日本二区| 一级片免费观看大全| 中文字幕人妻丝袜一区二区| 欧美日韩黄片免| 欧美乱码精品一区二区三区| 99热这里只有精品一区 | 亚洲一码二码三码区别大吗| 精品无人区乱码1区二区| svipshipincom国产片| 欧美日韩瑟瑟在线播放| av欧美777| 一个人免费在线观看电影 | 夜夜躁狠狠躁天天躁| 精品福利观看| 十八禁网站免费在线| 欧美成狂野欧美在线观看| 两个人看的免费小视频| 天天一区二区日本电影三级| 国产黄片美女视频| 国产私拍福利视频在线观看| 1024视频免费在线观看| 亚洲人成网站高清观看| 国产精品免费视频内射| 亚洲18禁久久av| 禁无遮挡网站| 色av中文字幕| 国产视频一区二区在线看| 精品国产美女av久久久久小说| 18美女黄网站色大片免费观看| 伦理电影免费视频| 999久久久精品免费观看国产| 亚洲精品色激情综合| 嫁个100分男人电影在线观看| 国产又黄又爽又无遮挡在线| 国产精品综合久久久久久久免费| 成在线人永久免费视频| 国产精品永久免费网站| 我的老师免费观看完整版| 亚洲精品国产精品久久久不卡| 99在线视频只有这里精品首页| 日韩大尺度精品在线看网址| 男女午夜视频在线观看| 国产精品久久久久久人妻精品电影| 99热这里只有精品一区 | 亚洲专区中文字幕在线| 国内毛片毛片毛片毛片毛片| 日本三级黄在线观看| 在线a可以看的网站| 91麻豆精品激情在线观看国产| 日韩高清综合在线| 免费一级毛片在线播放高清视频| 久久国产乱子伦精品免费另类| а√天堂www在线а√下载| 欧美3d第一页| 又紧又爽又黄一区二区| 九色成人免费人妻av| 国产成人av教育| 亚洲国产日韩欧美精品在线观看 | 亚洲全国av大片| 五月玫瑰六月丁香| 桃色一区二区三区在线观看| 国产精品1区2区在线观看.| 国产精品久久久人人做人人爽| 俺也久久电影网| 伦理电影免费视频| 99久久久亚洲精品蜜臀av| av有码第一页| 午夜福利成人在线免费观看| 999久久久精品免费观看国产| 国产亚洲欧美在线一区二区| 成人三级做爰电影| 老司机靠b影院| 国产精品日韩av在线免费观看| 日本撒尿小便嘘嘘汇集6| 特级一级黄色大片| 免费电影在线观看免费观看| 日本一区二区免费在线视频| 欧美不卡视频在线免费观看 | 国产亚洲精品综合一区在线观看 | 久久国产精品人妻蜜桃| 人人妻,人人澡人人爽秒播| 国产精品精品国产色婷婷| 久久草成人影院| 亚洲av五月六月丁香网| 一二三四社区在线视频社区8| 日本一区二区免费在线视频| 国产精品1区2区在线观看.| 亚洲18禁久久av| av片东京热男人的天堂| 又紧又爽又黄一区二区| 国产精品精品国产色婷婷| 99热这里只有精品一区 | 国产男靠女视频免费网站| 日日干狠狠操夜夜爽| 精品久久久久久久久久久久久| 亚洲精品中文字幕在线视频| 亚洲一码二码三码区别大吗| 久久 成人 亚洲| 成人三级黄色视频| 两性夫妻黄色片| 日日夜夜操网爽| 国产野战对白在线观看| www.www免费av| 精品一区二区三区av网在线观看| 精品久久久久久,| 狠狠狠狠99中文字幕| 日韩欧美在线二视频| 久久国产精品影院| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| www国产在线视频色| 在线观看66精品国产| 变态另类丝袜制服| 校园春色视频在线观看| 999久久久国产精品视频| 日韩欧美免费精品| 91老司机精品| 亚洲自拍偷在线| 色精品久久人妻99蜜桃| 亚洲欧美日韩高清在线视频| 巨乳人妻的诱惑在线观看| 日韩高清综合在线| 不卡av一区二区三区| 亚洲激情在线av| 国产成人aa在线观看| 亚洲va日本ⅴa欧美va伊人久久| 国产91精品成人一区二区三区| 亚洲成人久久爱视频| 不卡av一区二区三区| 免费在线观看完整版高清| 老司机午夜十八禁免费视频| 欧美三级亚洲精品| 欧美成人性av电影在线观看| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜添小说| 亚洲国产精品999在线| 在线观看午夜福利视频| 国产伦一二天堂av在线观看| 国产高清视频在线观看网站| 午夜福利成人在线免费观看| 日韩欧美国产一区二区入口| 日本一二三区视频观看| 日韩精品中文字幕看吧| 琪琪午夜伦伦电影理论片6080| 亚洲欧美精品综合一区二区三区| 日本精品一区二区三区蜜桃| 可以免费在线观看a视频的电影网站| 中文资源天堂在线| 亚洲va日本ⅴa欧美va伊人久久| 久久 成人 亚洲| 欧美精品啪啪一区二区三区| 麻豆国产97在线/欧美 | 国产av在哪里看| 久久久久国内视频| 亚洲自偷自拍图片 自拍| 丰满人妻一区二区三区视频av | 丝袜美腿诱惑在线| 两个人看的免费小视频| 一区福利在线观看| 午夜精品在线福利| 午夜激情av网站| 国产一区二区激情短视频| 亚洲国产中文字幕在线视频| 精品人妻1区二区| 18禁裸乳无遮挡免费网站照片| 亚洲中文日韩欧美视频| 国产精品免费一区二区三区在线| 可以免费在线观看a视频的电影网站| 国产午夜福利久久久久久| 我要搜黄色片| 精品久久久久久久人妻蜜臀av| 久久这里只有精品中国| 久久精品国产99精品国产亚洲性色| 一区二区三区激情视频| 国产成人精品无人区| 国产探花在线观看一区二区| 亚洲激情在线av| 国产亚洲欧美98| 一区二区三区激情视频| 国产精品综合久久久久久久免费| 夜夜看夜夜爽夜夜摸| 久久伊人香网站| 亚洲欧美日韩高清在线视频| 一区二区三区国产精品乱码| 一级毛片女人18水好多| 国产亚洲精品综合一区在线观看 | 中亚洲国语对白在线视频| 中出人妻视频一区二区| 久久精品国产综合久久久| 12—13女人毛片做爰片一| 长腿黑丝高跟| 久久香蕉激情| 亚洲一区二区三区不卡视频| 国产精品av视频在线免费观看| 又大又爽又粗| 欧美乱码精品一区二区三区| 香蕉av资源在线| 午夜激情福利司机影院| 成人永久免费在线观看视频| 88av欧美| 热99re8久久精品国产| 亚洲一区二区三区不卡视频| 国内揄拍国产精品人妻在线| 国产av又大| 搡老熟女国产l中国老女人| 18禁国产床啪视频网站| 99热6这里只有精品| 午夜激情av网站| 露出奶头的视频| 国产人伦9x9x在线观看| 大型黄色视频在线免费观看| 亚洲av第一区精品v没综合| 91老司机精品| avwww免费| 18禁黄网站禁片午夜丰满| 国产精品98久久久久久宅男小说| 宅男免费午夜| 亚洲欧美激情综合另类| 老熟妇乱子伦视频在线观看| 亚洲精品色激情综合| 久久这里只有精品19| 欧美性长视频在线观看| 丰满的人妻完整版| 三级毛片av免费| 手机成人av网站| 亚洲中文av在线| 一本精品99久久精品77| 不卡一级毛片| 99久久无色码亚洲精品果冻| 丁香六月欧美| 国产一区在线观看成人免费| 成年人黄色毛片网站| 亚洲国产欧美网| 美女大奶头视频| 国产成人精品久久二区二区91| 亚洲国产精品久久男人天堂| 亚洲国产精品999在线| 很黄的视频免费| 成人av一区二区三区在线看| 欧美人与性动交α欧美精品济南到| 久久国产精品影院| 99riav亚洲国产免费| 老熟妇乱子伦视频在线观看| a级毛片在线看网站| 久久久久国产精品人妻aⅴ院| 少妇裸体淫交视频免费看高清 | 国产精品一及| 国产片内射在线| 国产精品av视频在线免费观看| 可以免费在线观看a视频的电影网站| 女同久久另类99精品国产91| 88av欧美| 日本 av在线| 男插女下体视频免费在线播放| 亚洲成av人片在线播放无| 丰满的人妻完整版| e午夜精品久久久久久久| 亚洲午夜精品一区,二区,三区| 亚洲熟妇中文字幕五十中出| 夜夜夜夜夜久久久久| 久久香蕉精品热| 18禁美女被吸乳视频| 亚洲天堂国产精品一区在线| 欧美 亚洲 国产 日韩一| 国产精品av视频在线免费观看| av福利片在线| 看片在线看免费视频| 国产精品久久久久久亚洲av鲁大| 丝袜美腿诱惑在线| 熟女少妇亚洲综合色aaa.| 国产精品99久久99久久久不卡| 久久天堂一区二区三区四区| 久9热在线精品视频| 国产精品野战在线观看| av中文乱码字幕在线| 搡老妇女老女人老熟妇| 国产成人啪精品午夜网站| 久久香蕉精品热| 欧美一区二区国产精品久久精品 | 中文字幕av在线有码专区| 欧美黑人精品巨大| 三级毛片av免费| 久久久久精品国产欧美久久久| 日韩高清综合在线| 色综合婷婷激情| 88av欧美| 熟女少妇亚洲综合色aaa.| 国产精品影院久久| 一级a爱片免费观看的视频| 1024视频免费在线观看| 国产精品亚洲美女久久久| 丰满的人妻完整版| 最新在线观看一区二区三区| 国产午夜精品论理片| 国产av一区二区精品久久| 真人一进一出gif抽搐免费| 熟妇人妻久久中文字幕3abv| 99精品欧美一区二区三区四区| 最新在线观看一区二区三区| 巨乳人妻的诱惑在线观看| 老司机福利观看| 美女免费视频网站| svipshipincom国产片| 国产精品久久久人人做人人爽| 黄色丝袜av网址大全| 91麻豆精品激情在线观看国产| 中文字幕最新亚洲高清| 老汉色av国产亚洲站长工具| 人人妻人人看人人澡| 床上黄色一级片| 欧美最黄视频在线播放免费| videosex国产| 91九色精品人成在线观看| 国内毛片毛片毛片毛片毛片| 激情在线观看视频在线高清| 日韩高清综合在线| 麻豆久久精品国产亚洲av| 麻豆成人午夜福利视频| 亚洲av成人不卡在线观看播放网| 桃色一区二区三区在线观看| 国产又色又爽无遮挡免费看| 国产成人啪精品午夜网站| 色综合亚洲欧美另类图片| 成人18禁高潮啪啪吃奶动态图| 国产精品,欧美在线| 观看免费一级毛片| 久久香蕉国产精品| 国产亚洲精品一区二区www| 免费观看人在逋| www日本在线高清视频| 母亲3免费完整高清在线观看| 国产精品98久久久久久宅男小说| 两性夫妻黄色片| 一区二区三区高清视频在线| 美女 人体艺术 gogo| 国产野战对白在线观看| 国产激情久久老熟女| 国产精品av视频在线免费观看| 中文字幕最新亚洲高清| 19禁男女啪啪无遮挡网站| 午夜日韩欧美国产| 少妇裸体淫交视频免费看高清 | 18禁黄网站禁片午夜丰满| 全区人妻精品视频| 麻豆成人午夜福利视频| 日本五十路高清| 性欧美人与动物交配| 国产一区在线观看成人免费| 欧美大码av| 99久久精品热视频| 国产精品一区二区免费欧美| 久久精品影院6| 欧美高清成人免费视频www| 国产黄色小视频在线观看| 丁香六月欧美| 国产av不卡久久| 国产99久久九九免费精品| 国产亚洲欧美在线一区二区| 熟妇人妻久久中文字幕3abv| 1024视频免费在线观看| 两个人的视频大全免费| 两人在一起打扑克的视频| 国产一区在线观看成人免费| 最近最新中文字幕大全电影3| 国产精品一区二区三区四区久久| 国产成人精品久久二区二区免费| 国产黄色小视频在线观看| 亚洲午夜精品一区,二区,三区| 午夜福利在线观看吧| 在线观看www视频免费| 狂野欧美白嫩少妇大欣赏| 亚洲真实伦在线观看| 中出人妻视频一区二区| 宅男免费午夜| 看黄色毛片网站| 露出奶头的视频| 免费一级毛片在线播放高清视频| 亚洲精品色激情综合| svipshipincom国产片| 国产不卡一卡二| svipshipincom国产片| 亚洲国产欧洲综合997久久,| 亚洲午夜理论影院| 夜夜爽天天搞| 国产一区二区三区视频了| 热99re8久久精品国产| 美女大奶头视频| 天堂影院成人在线观看| 亚洲av日韩精品久久久久久密| 99国产精品一区二区三区| 老鸭窝网址在线观看| 亚洲电影在线观看av| 在线观看免费午夜福利视频| www日本黄色视频网| 最近最新中文字幕大全电影3| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 亚洲中文字幕一区二区三区有码在线看 | 女同久久另类99精品国产91| 免费在线观看黄色视频的| 亚洲成人精品中文字幕电影| 国产高清videossex| 久久久水蜜桃国产精品网| 国产午夜精品论理片| 色精品久久人妻99蜜桃| 18禁观看日本| 婷婷丁香在线五月| 国产高清视频在线观看网站| 久久精品国产综合久久久| 久久亚洲真实| 国内少妇人妻偷人精品xxx网站 | 亚洲最大成人中文| 国产成人影院久久av| 精品电影一区二区在线| 国产v大片淫在线免费观看| 亚洲成人国产一区在线观看| 99久久99久久久精品蜜桃| 久久亚洲真实| 精品电影一区二区在线| 熟女少妇亚洲综合色aaa.| 亚洲精品美女久久久久99蜜臀| 亚洲av成人一区二区三| 久久久久久大精品| 色综合婷婷激情| 亚洲人成77777在线视频| 哪里可以看免费的av片| 亚洲国产精品久久男人天堂| 1024香蕉在线观看| 欧美久久黑人一区二区| 99精品欧美一区二区三区四区| 脱女人内裤的视频| 亚洲熟妇中文字幕五十中出| 淫妇啪啪啪对白视频| 天堂√8在线中文| 一级毛片精品| 精品久久久久久久毛片微露脸| 国产熟女xx| 精品免费久久久久久久清纯| 99国产精品一区二区三区| 欧美黑人巨大hd| 国产精品亚洲一级av第二区| 在线观看午夜福利视频| 亚洲中文字幕一区二区三区有码在线看 | 男女下面进入的视频免费午夜| 高清在线国产一区| 亚洲精品美女久久久久99蜜臀| 亚洲午夜精品一区,二区,三区| 在线观看午夜福利视频| 亚洲欧美精品综合一区二区三区| 一进一出好大好爽视频| 老司机福利观看| 男女下面进入的视频免费午夜| 亚洲第一电影网av| 国产精品久久久人人做人人爽| 50天的宝宝边吃奶边哭怎么回事| 99在线人妻在线中文字幕| 亚洲av片天天在线观看| 性色av乱码一区二区三区2| 欧美日本视频| 男女之事视频高清在线观看| 国内精品一区二区在线观看| а√天堂www在线а√下载| 免费无遮挡裸体视频| www.www免费av| 少妇粗大呻吟视频| 最新在线观看一区二区三区| 亚洲国产看品久久| 亚洲欧美精品综合久久99| 欧美黑人精品巨大| 亚洲国产中文字幕在线视频| 日韩欧美一区二区三区在线观看| 国产aⅴ精品一区二区三区波| 亚洲av美国av| 老司机深夜福利视频在线观看| 后天国语完整版免费观看| 国产一区在线观看成人免费| 99热这里只有是精品50| 制服丝袜大香蕉在线| 欧美三级亚洲精品| 99久久综合精品五月天人人| 久久精品影院6| 白带黄色成豆腐渣| 国产精品美女特级片免费视频播放器 | 午夜福利高清视频| 法律面前人人平等表现在哪些方面| 国产午夜精品久久久久久| 国产精品99久久99久久久不卡| 国内精品久久久久久久电影| 1024香蕉在线观看| 欧美 亚洲 国产 日韩一| 久久香蕉激情| 国产av一区二区精品久久| 亚洲国产日韩欧美精品在线观看 | 国产精品 国内视频| 久久久久亚洲av毛片大全| 最新美女视频免费是黄的| 免费看美女性在线毛片视频| 精品国产亚洲在线| 人妻久久中文字幕网| 欧美日韩中文字幕国产精品一区二区三区| 亚洲精品一卡2卡三卡4卡5卡| 国产成人一区二区三区免费视频网站| 1024香蕉在线观看| 亚洲va日本ⅴa欧美va伊人久久| 久99久视频精品免费| 免费av毛片视频| 国产熟女xx| 国产熟女午夜一区二区三区| 在线观看一区二区三区| 久久久久久久久中文| 91国产中文字幕| 男人舔女人下体高潮全视频| 亚洲午夜理论影院| 日本一二三区视频观看| 美女午夜性视频免费| 真人做人爱边吃奶动态| 一本久久中文字幕| 国产真人三级小视频在线观看| 男男h啪啪无遮挡| 这个男人来自地球电影免费观看| 无遮挡黄片免费观看| 日韩欧美国产在线观看| а√天堂www在线а√下载| 嫩草影视91久久| www.熟女人妻精品国产| 亚洲九九香蕉| 三级国产精品欧美在线观看 | 欧美绝顶高潮抽搐喷水| 国产成人aa在线观看| 亚洲激情在线av| 欧美性长视频在线观看| 午夜老司机福利片| 99精品欧美一区二区三区四区| 午夜激情av网站| 久久久国产成人精品二区| 国产一区二区激情短视频| 一区二区三区激情视频|