• <tr id="yyy80"></tr>
  • <sup id="yyy80"></sup>
  • <tfoot id="yyy80"><noscript id="yyy80"></noscript></tfoot>
  • 99热精品在线国产_美女午夜性视频免费_国产精品国产高清国产av_av欧美777_自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇_亚洲熟女精品中文字幕_www日本黄色视频网_国产精品野战在线观看 ?

    Academic Differences between the Guanzhong School and the Yangming School in the Middle Ming Dynasty

    2020-07-18 16:17:44ChangXin
    孔學(xué)堂 2020年2期
    關(guān)鍵詞:樊遲關(guān)學(xué)顏淵

    Chang Xin

    Abstract: The revivalistic literary movement during the Hongzhi reign of the Ming dynasty aimed for literary renovation and at the same time triggered self-reflection and self-criticism within Confucianism. Sharing a common literary pursuit and political ideal, Guanzhong scholars Li Mengyang, Kang Hai, and Wang Jiusi, together with Wang Yangming, participated in that revivalistic literary movement. Later, however, Wang Yangming shifted his focus to reforming Confucianism and proposed the doctrine of intuitive knowledge, which broke the dominance of the Cheng–Zhu school of principle in Confucianism. In the face of the radical change Wang Yangming brought to Confucianism, the Guanzhong scholars distanced themselves from Wang with their responses to Wangs theories of intuitive knowledge, investigating things, knowledge and action, and gongfu, indicating that the Guanzhong school was following Zhu Xi in its pursuit of Neo-Confucianism.

    Keywords: Guanzhong school, Yangming school, academic differences, middle Ming dynasty

    The Hongzhi period (1488–1505) in the Ming dynasty (1368–1644) witnessed a revivalistic literary movement, and after it there occurred a political struggle against Liu Jin 劉瑾 (1451–1510), a powerful eunuch who was favored by the then emperor. In this movement and struggle, the renowned early Seven Scholars, namely, Kang Hai 康海 (1475–1541), Li Mengyang 李夢(mèng)陽 (1473–1529), Wang Jiusi 王九思 (1468–1551), He Jingming 何景明 (1483–1521), Xu Zhenqing 徐禎卿 (1479–1511), Bian Gong 邊貢 (1476–1532), and Wang Tingxiang 王廷相 (1474–1544), as well as some other influential scholars such as Lü Nan 呂柟 (1479–1542, style name Jingye 涇野) and Wang Yangming 王陽明 (1472–1528, a.k.a. Wang Shouren 王守仁) formed a group with shared values. Their scholarly interactions promoted the development of scholarship in the Ming dynasty. Of the early Seven Scholars, Li Mengyang, Kang Hai, and Wang Jiusi were scholars of Guanxue 關(guān)學(xué) (the Guanzhong school). They had personal contacts with Wang Yangming himself and, in addition, in their careers as officials, they associated with some disciples of Wang Yangming, and through exchanges of ideas and debates over academic questions, both sides got to know each others opinions well, which indicated their academic differences.

    The main reasons why the Guanzhong scholars opposed Wang Yangming and his followers, in regard to the major aspects of Wangs philosophy, are manifold. First, the Guanzhong scholars were firm followers of Zhu Xi 朱熹 (1130–1200). Second, many Guanzhong scholars understanding of Wang Yangmings philosophy was based on secondhand materials and consequently deviated from what it meant originally to say. Third, when Wang was alive, differences in understanding his doctrine already occurred among his disciples. After he passed away, his disciples split into many sub-schools, and later some disciples of his gave up self-cultivation and got lost in seeking sudden enlightenment, whose empty and shallow academic style was unacceptable to the Guanzhong Confucians who cherished honesty and sincerity in their scholarly pursuit, thus causing their misunderstanding and rejection of Wangs teachings.

    Difference on the Doctrine of Intuitive Knowledge

    [Refer to page 85 for Chinese. Similarly hereinafter]

    The root of Wang Yangmings philosophy is the doctrine of intuitive knowledge (liangzhi 良知), comprising two aspects: (1) the original substance of intuitive knowledge and (2) the effort (gongfu 工夫) to extend intuitive knowledge (zhi liangzhi 致良知). It can be known from Wang Yangmings clarification of his concept of intuitive knowledge that, in conceiving his doctrine of intuitive knowledge, he drew on the relevant theories of Confucianism, Buddhism, and Daoism and integrated them into his theory. His approach to developing a new doctrine introduced a new realm of theorization within Confucianism, but at the same time provoked strong criticism against his doctrine among his contemporary and later Confucians, who blamed its closeness to the doctrine of the Chan Sect of Buddhism. His concept of intuitive knowledge became the object which bore the brunt of their censure and attack. In the debates of Guanzhong scholars with Wang and his followers, the question of intuitive knowledge was frequently a hot topic. Though admitting that “Wangs doctrine is based on Menciuss theory on intuitive knowledge, and when Wang proposed it to instruct people, its warning was not insignificant,” Lü Nans difference from Wang is considerable over the question of intuitive knowledge.

    As regards Lüs comment on Wangs doctrine of intuitive knowledge, little is mentioned in the records available. Nonetheless, in the preface to “Presented to Shi in Yuxi” [贈(zèng)玉溪石氏] are a few important sentences which make it clear that he called it into question.

    Compared with me who has been accused and exiled once again, Wang Yangming has climbed higher and higher up the official ladder, his path has become wider and wider, and the people who spread and advocate his doctrine are more and more. . . . His doctrine is quite different from the opinion I expounded initially to the official historian. . . . These days I am eager to see Wang so as to resolve my doubt. . . . But up to this time I have not had any chance to consult him.

    It is a pity that after pacifying a rebellion in the Sien Prefecture and Tianzhou Prefecture, Wang Yangming died of an illness and Lü could never see him and discuss with him any longer the doctrine from which he had felt “quite different.” The reason for Lüs complaint about Wangs intuitive knowledge is mainly that, to him, Wangs doctrine of intuitive knowledge ignored the individual difference in natural endowment. He mentioned this problem with Wangs doctrine in both his “Record of Yangzhi Pavilion” [仰止亭記] and his “Discourse from East Abode in Jiufeng Peak” [鷲峰東所語], in either of which the recorded conversations of Lü were with some of Wangs disciples who firmly believed in their masters doctrine.

    When the Sage (i.e., Confucius) taught his students, he would change his method of teaching with different students. For example, when Yan Yuan 顏淵 (521–481 BCE) asked him what was meant by ren 仁 (humanity), Confucius told him that it meant “restraining oneself and returning to propriety.” To answer the same question asked by Zhonnggong 仲弓 (b. 522 BCE), Confucius told him to respect others and avoid resentment. To Fan Chi 樊遲 (d. 515 BCE) who asked the same question, Confucius replied by saying: “It is, in retirement, to be sedately reverent; in the management of business, to be earnestly attentive; in association with others, to be strictly sincere.” This shows that he taught his students according to their different natural endowments and the different levels of their advancements in learning, avoiding applying the same rigid standard. By contrast, when contemporary Confucians taught others, they tended to neglect their different natural endowments and actual advancements, and impose on them the same requirements. Are they not biased?

    On the individual difference in natural endowment, Lü was of the opinion that Wangs doctrine of intuitive knowledge might take effect on those with natural endowment above the middle, but was completely to no avail to those below the middle. The issues of human natural endowment and the acceptability of Wang Yangmings doctrine Lü mentioned in his “Record of Yangzhi Pavilion” may have to do with the elucidation Wang made of his Four-Sentence Teachingsi on an occasion when his two disciples Wang Ji 王畿 (1498–1583) and Qian Dehong 錢德洪 (1496–1574) debated it, an incident which was referred to as “Elucidation on Heavenly Fountain Bridge.” Wang Yangming said to them,

    My doctrine always embraces these two instructions: The four no-distinctionsii are an instruction for those endowed with the top-level root, while the four distinctions are an instruction for those with the middle-level and the lower-level root. To those with the upper root, the original substance is the same as gongfu, which pertains to the pursuit of sudden enlightenment. To those with middle and lower root, they have to make an effort to do good and remove evil so as to return to their original substance.

    Considering the above three opinions of Lü, it is obvious that, to him, hidden in Wangs doctrine of intuitive knowledge was something worrying: Those people endowed with a lower root could by no means understand truly his doctrine, and this failure would prompt misunderstanding and misreading on their part, which would cause a series of problems to crop up. Actually, the many malpractices which occurred among Wangs followers after he passed away were the very problems he was worried about. It can be known from this that Wangs doctrine of intuitive knowledge was troubled by some theoretical drawbacks and defects, and Lü, as an onlooker, was clearly aware of them.

    In his discussions of cognition by the mind (xin 心) and nature (xing 性), Ma Li 馬理 (1474–1555, pen name Xitian 溪田), through differentiating several types of “knowledge” (zhi 知), clarified the subjects gongfu of self-cultivation in different phases and also distinguished between the intuitive knowledge emanating from the innocent minds of children and the hidden subtle knowledge one could only get access to by keeping watchful while alone and making an effort to cultivate oneself. At the same time, the knowledge that is extended through investigation of things (gewu 格物) is obviously tinted with the epistemology in the tradition of Cheng Yi 程頤 (1033–1107) and Zhu Xi, that is, the great knowledge is extended by seeking for a sudden apprehension of the total substance through long-term accumulation by persistently investigating things and exhausting principle to the utmost. The former two types of knowledge pertain to moral cognition, while the knowledge extended through investigation of things falls into the category of rational experiential cognition. Thereby, in his criticism, Ma said, “Their teacher had claimed, ‘this knowledge is the same as that knowledge, and they spoke of it as gaining understanding half way and compared it to awakening from a dream. They sounded like followers of Chan Buddhism indeed.” Though he did not mention whom he drove at, clearly what he said pointed at the empty talk about the doctrine of morality, nature, and destiny prevalent among the later Yangming scholars.

    Hu Zuanzong 胡纘宗 (1480–1560) once had a deep discussion with Wang Yangming at Liantan Posthouse (in todays Tongcheng of Anhui) over the question of investigating things and extending knowledge to the utmost, but they did not touch upon the concept of intuitive knowledge. In his Wishing for Learning [愿學(xué)編], Hu did not endorse Wangs doctrine of intuitive knowledge, and believing that Wangs doctrine of intuitive knowledge was different from Menciuss doctrine of intuitive knowledge, he expressed his doubt about Wangs extending intuitive knowledge.

    In the Great Learning, it is zhi zhi 致知 (extending knowledge), while now they use zhi liangzhi. Could it be that there are two different zhi 知? As there exists only one li 理 (principle), so there exists only one knowledge which should be extended. When they say “the intuitive knowledge seems unnecessary to be extended,” this means that innocent children can extend their knowledge naturally by themselves. But when they say “they extend it so as to make themselves never lose their intuitive knowledge,” does this not mean “they extend it so as to make themselves never lose their original mind”? Is this not confusing? Is it necessary to mention “intuitive knowledge”? Their so called intuitive knowledge is nothing but knowledge itself.

    Hu shared the opinion of Lü that knowledge pertained to Heavenly principle (天理), and it possessed the attribute of being intuitive, so the term “intuitive knowledge” was tautological. Since, according to him, intuitive knowledge was possessed by humankind a priori, it did not need a posteriori effort to extend it, and in this sense, in the expression “extending intuitive knowledge” there is a logical contradiction. Hu here ignored Wang Yangmings idea that the a priori “intuitive” did not necessarily lead to the a posteriori “intuitive,” and the veiling of the “intuitive” caused by the profane in human life was the very reason why the a priori “intuitive” was lost. It is because of this ignorance that Hu also distanced himself from Wang in regard to his understanding of the investigation of things.

    Difference on the Concept of Investigating Things [87]

    Wang Yangming, in his early years, tried to understand Zhu Xis concept of investigating things, but felt perplexed by it. On the basis of his study of the ancient text of the Great Learning, Wang suspected that Zhus Interpretation of the Great Learning [大學(xué)章句] fell short of revealing the original intention of the Confucian classic. In 1508, Wang attained a thorough understanding of Confucian philosophy at Longchang and this unraveled his perplexity over the concept of investigating things. He said, “I understand the doctrine of the sage that tells me my nature is self-sufficient, and I was wrong to look for principles in things and affairs.” According to his understanding, the “investigating” means rectifying and the “things” refers to affairs. Thus, his explanation of the concept is rectifying the will, that is, setting right what is not right in the mind so that the mind can return to the rightness possessed by the original substance.

    However, after Wang proposed his explanation of investigating things, it was called into question by a number of Neo-Confucians belonging to the school of principle. For example, Lü Nan, who inherited Zhu Xis theory of investigating things and extending knowledge, reiterated that investigating things was nothing but probing the principle to the utmost. Here, “principle” does not refer to objective knowledge in the usual sense, nor to the transcendental Heavenly principle, but rather the principle underlying daily activities and behaviors. Therefore, he was opposed to Wang and his followers who understood investigating things as rectifying the mind. Furthermore, he criticized Luo Jinxi 羅近溪 (1515–1588) who proposed that “intuitive knowledge was ready-made,” for his theory further misled the later Yangming scholars who were lost in the bad practice of seeking for sudden enlightenment but slighting gongfu and practice. According to Lü, “The Way advocated by the Confucian sages was very simple, plain, and easy, which only needed one to practice it in his daily activities and behaviors, and whatever theory preached anything occult, elusive, and too high to be reachable was heretical.”

    A detailed record of the discussion on the question of investigating things between Hu Zuanzong and Wang Yangming can be found in Hus Wishing for Learning. Their conversation indicates that they had some common ground over that question, but it does not follow that Hu agreed completely with Wangs opinion of investigating things. According to Hu, Wang was wrong when he understood “things” as will, for they were two separate concepts which were not related to each other at all. Wang explained “things” as “things in the will,” and took them as the object of investigating. To him, since this object entered into a substantial relationship with the subject in the latters cognition and practice, it acquired meaning for humankind. In Hus sense, the “things” refers to the things in the physical world, which involves both the known part and the unknown part, and in the unknown part, there is no meaning to speak of. In this regard, their difference is mainly concerned with their different understandings of the denotation and connotation of “things.”

    As Wang explained, the “investigating” and “things” mean respectively rectifying and affairs, and he defined the “affairs” as what the will dwells in. In his sense, investigating things means rectifying what is not right in the mind. Thus, he replaced the cognitive function played by investigating things in Zhu Xis sense with the simple and rapid function of setting right the immoral consciousness. In light of Wangs logic, the things are where the will dwells and the arousing and functioning of the mind concern it. This means that extending knowledge occurs before investigating things. As the function of the will, rectifying plays at the same time the roles of extending knowledge, making the will sincere, and rectifying the mind, thus making it unnecessary for one to pursue learning by following the “three items and eight steps” (三綱八目) as Confucianism advocated. For this reason, Hu criticized Wangs explanation of investigating things for its neglecting probing external things and turning the pursuit of learning completely into an internal psychological activity, and he blamed its destructive and subversive deviation from the traditional interpretation of investigating things transmitted in the Confucian classics.

    Difference on the Relationship between Knowledge and Action [88]

    In 1509, the second year after Wang Yangming had his thorough realization of the Confucian philosophy at Longchang, he put forward his theory of knowledge and action in unity (知行合一). In that year, Lü Nan served as an official in the capital. One year later, he submitted a memorial to the throne against Liu Jin, the powerful eunuch, and to avoid political persecution, he resigned on the pretext of illness and then returned to his hometown. Thenceforth, he made clear his opinion on Wang Yangmings theory of knowledge and action while discussing academic issues with Zhan Ruoshui 湛若水 (1466–1560).

    Zhan was the official in charge of the highest imperial civil examination Lü Nan took and passed. In his pursuit of learning, Lü benefited much from Zhan, and actually, he conceived his theory of “knowledge being prior to action” under Zhans influence. In his opinion, Zhans theory of “advancing knowledge and action side by side” could be adopted to remedy Wangs theory of “knowledge and action in unity.” However, Lü misunderstood Wang slightly here, for Wang never treated knowledge and action as two separate things, but highlighted their unity. As Wang said, “Knowledge is the direction for action and action is the gongfu of knowledge. Knowledge is the beginning of action, and action the completion of knowledge.” Of knowledge and action, Wang attached more importance to action. “There have never been people who know but do not act, for those who are supposed to know but do not act simply do not yet know.” In essence, Zhans “advancing knowledge and action side by side” was another expression of Wangs “knowledge and action in unity.” Therefore, Lüs agreement with Zhans theory of advancing knowledge and action side by side can be seen as his indirect agreement with Wangs theory of knowledge and action in unity.

    Lü Nans understanding of Wang Yangmings theory of knowledge and action in unity is not based on his direct reading of Wangs works but on some indirect sources, that is, some hearsay information and even misreading of Wangs theory held by later Yangming scholars. Wangs basic idea was to stress gongfu and action, emphasizing the manifestation of the original substance through gongfu, but sometimes indeed Wang expounded the original substance of intuitive knowledge as something too elusive and mysterious. In particular, his affirmation of Wang Jis theory of four no-distinctions led directly to the left-wing Yangming scholars pursuing a direct enlightenment which transcended the original substance, neglecting the requirement for accumulating effects by making simple and superficial efforts persistently. Thus, those scholars were lost in the bad practice of pursuing what was empty, mysterious, visionary, and far away, treating it as their final destination. By contrast, Lüs study of humanity (仁學(xué)) is characterized by his saying little of the original substance and his emphasizing gongfu and practice whenever and wherever. Therefore, from his own standpoint, he warned other scholars against too much talk about the elusive original substance of intuitive knowledge. His contribution lay in reminding them of the possible negative consequences caused by the doctrine of intuitive knowledge and rectifying its deviation. Later, in the transition from the Ming dynasty to the Qing dynasty (1644–1911), when some scholars of the Guanzhong school criticized the empty and shallow academic style taken up by the later Yangming scholars, their scholarship was under direct influence from Lü, who cherished and displayed the sincere and earnest spirit of the Guanzhong school in its pursuit of learning.

    Hu Zuanzong, in his Wishing for Learning, refuted point by point Wang Yangmings exposition of his theory of knowledge and action. From Hus arguments, it is obvious that Hu was very familiar with Wangs exposition on the question of knowledge and action, as well as Wangs letters where he discussed that question with other scholars. In Hus opinion, knowledge and action should not be integrated as one but rather be seen as two interrelated processes. As for the simile “[one] hates what smells bad or loves what looks beautiful,” which Wang employed when he explained his view of knowledge and action, Hu only attributed the “hate” and “l(fā)ove” to the category of knowledge, and to put that knowledge into the practice of action one had to make some effort. If one had that knowledge but failed to act (that is, he did not go beyond the step of knowing), it meant that he did not complete the entire process of knowing and acting. In this regard, Hu noted that, to complete the entire process of knowing and acting, their subject had to enter into a substantial practical relationship with the object of his knowledge and action. “When one has not drawn near to what looks beautiful and has not kept far away from what smells bad, then it should not be said that he has acted,” said Hu. Wang Yangmings disciple Xu Ai 徐愛 (1487–1518) raised questions over his proposition that knowledge and action were a unity. When explaining his theory to Xu, Wang cited coldness, hunger, loyalty, and filial piety as examples. In this regard, Hu stood on the side of Xu and affirmed that knowledge and action were clearly two separate things. For if lacking the necessary conditions, despite having knowledge of coldness and hunger and despite having knowledge of loyalty and filial piety, one could never put the knowledge into action, then this could not be said to be his action. As Wang said,

    The reason why I proposed my theory of knowledge and action in unity is that recent scholars have tended to separate them as two different things, that is, pursuing knowledge before putting it into action. However, deplorably, they would only end up with no action at all for all their life. Thus, I have had to use it to rectify their deviation and correct their bad practices.

    Denying Wang Yangmings theory of knowledge and action in unity, Hu asked, “To know what one should know and do what one should do—is there anything that the ancients did against their will? Anything that they had to rectify and correct?”

    In a word, on the relationship of knowledge and action, the main difference between the Guanzhong Confucians and Wang Yangming lies in whether they should be seen as a unity or treated as two separate processes. Despite the theoretical defect with Wangs theory of knowledge and action as a unity, it was somewhat reasonable in that it displayed his anxiety about contemporary scholars, who separated them as two separate things and who eventually failed to turn to action. With their criticism targeting Wangs theory, the Guanzhong scholars, including Lü Nan and Hu Zuanzong, intended to highlight the importance of action, under the precondition of attaching importance to knowledge. In this regard, the Yangming school and the Guanzhong school shared some common ground in their theories. However, when Wang, under the premise of his theory of knowledge and action as a unity, claimed that “the moment an idea stirs, action occurs,” its theoretical insufficiency was obvious, and it became an object of denunciation from his opponents.

    Difference on the Theory of Gongfu [90]

    In the recorded discussions of Wang Yangming with other scholars and in his letters, there are abundant materials concerning the question of tranquility (jing 靜). As recorded in the “Chronicle of Wang Shourens Life” [年譜], in 1510, Wang “and his disciples sat in tranquility in a Buddhist temple, and he guided them to seek for personal understanding of the substance of nature, and they felt as if there was something accessible.” Though his gongfu of tranquility has a somewhat mysterious nature, he made it clear that,

    It must be known that if one strives for the gongfu of tranquility but does not make any effort to restrain himself or herself, then when anything occurs, one will be at a loss. One must train and polish himself or herself in the actual affairs of life. Only in this way can the one stand firm and keep unperturbed whether in tranquility or in activity.

    This is somewhat different from the Daoist or Buddhist gongfu in pursuit of tranquility. However, due to the later followers of Wang who made indiscriminate use of his concept of the gongfu of tranquility, many Confucian scholars questioned and criticized Wangs doctrine for its too strong tincture of Chan Buddhism.

    For Lü Nan, Wangs gongfu theory laid too much emphasis on sitting in tranquility, which might lead to the danger of neglecting the learning of concrete knowledge.

    Wang Yangming had experienced things and affairs of every kind, and in his old age, he took to sitting in tranquility and whenever his disciples came and asked questions of him, he would tell them to do as he did. How easy his Way was! But this is not the Way of Confucius, who was fond of antiquity and earnest in seeking it there, forgot his food in his eager pursuit of knowledge, and was the whole night without sleeping, and who never slackened in asking questions of others about propriety, officialdom, and such things. When the Sage was so diligent and painstaking, how much more should other men be? A scholar should exert himself in pursuit of learning day and night, and even by acting thus, he may fail to gain true knowledge, and even after gaining it, he may forget it.

    The main target of Lü Nans criticism cited above was those later Yangming scholars who talked much about sudden enlightenment but ignored self-cultivation. Actually, many other disciples of Wangs had already started to criticize them. As recorded by Qian Dehong, in Chuyang (in modern Chuzhou, Anhui Province) where Wang Yangming once advocated his doctrine and assisted people by teaching them the practice of sitting in tranquility, “there arose more and more scholars preaching empty views for the sake of offbeat novelty,” and Qian blamed them for their “merely sitting in tranquility but making no effort to examine and restrain themselves.” Huang Wan 黃綰 (1477–1551) also denounced those Yangming scholars for their “indulgence and lack of self-restraint.” Of his disciples, Qian and Huang were two who Wang thought highly of and their ideas to some extent represented Wangs own opinion on those topics.

    Yang Jue 楊爵 (1493–1549) and Qian Dehong were both imprisoned for years, and for three years during their imprisonments they kept in contact and discussed academic issues. Yang accepted Qians suggestion for the gongfu of tranquility, which can be demonstrated by the records Yang made.

    At the beginning of the night, I would sit in tranquility and make some examination of my words and deeds in the daytime. Having read Sima Guangs 司馬光 (1019–1086) discussion on the essentials of exerting the mind to the utmost and conducting oneself, I began by not talking nonsense. . . . With mental tranquility, I am able to know the springs of things, while if the mind is caught by disturbance, then it counts the perilous as safety and the calamitous as profit.

    But from the letters Qian wrote to Yang to discuss academic questions, it can be known that Yang called into question Wang Yangmings opinion that “the mind stirs when acted on by things.” In a letter, Qian also said, “Our teacher has left us for a long time, and I have no way to know whether what I heard about his teachings is what he really meant to say. Thus, today I can do nothing but confirm them by using my mind.” As regards the question concerned here, Yang Jue seemed inconsistent, but considering his circumstances in prison, we can understand the possibility and necessity of his gongfu by sitting in tranquility. Meanwhile, when Yang Jue, a Guanzhong scholar, distanced himself from Wang Yangming and adhered to the Guanzhong schools tradition of practicing personally the Confucian code of conduct, this conforms to the characteristic of the school.

    Of those Confucian scholars who were Wangs contemporaries, Ma Li was the harshest critic of Wangs doctrine. His “Letter Submitted to Master Luo Zhengan” [上羅整庵先生書] is the most important document for studying his thought and his academic difference from Wang Yangming. In the letter, Ma saw Wang and his disciples definitely as “followers of Chan Buddhism.” When it comes to how to understand the concept of keeping watchful while alone stated in the Doctrine of the Mean, Ma argued: “One should examine himself whenever there is any subtle spring of anything in his mind so as to prevent it from becoming vile and selfish and should keep cautious and apprehensive when in supreme tranquility so as to preserve the substantial principle.” The concept of hidden and subtle knowledge accessible only by keeping watchful while alone highlights the effort for moral practice of exerting nature to the utmost, practicing in person, preserving the mind, and examining oneself, and this what is meant by the approach of honoring moral nature, which naturally should not be neglected in light of the Confucian theory of gongfu. As for following the path of inquiry and study, pointing at the inclination among many later Yangming scholars to preach the pursuit of sudden enlightenment while ignoring self-cultivation, Ma was critical, saying,

    Nowadays, a rampant far-fetched argument claims that the sudden attainment of sagehood can be made and reading books may as well be dropped. They are self-indulgent, presumptuous, usurping, and pretentious even more than Yang Zhu 楊朱 (ca. 395–335) and Mo Di 墨翟 (468–376)! This vile stream actually started from Wang Yangming who was the first to advocate it.

    Though what Ma said against this inclination among the later followers of Wang Yangming was troubled by his misunderstanding to some extent of Wang himself and his scholarship, his criticism was not groundless.

    Conclusion [91]

    On the whole, in the middle Ming dynasty, the Guanzhong scholars were tolerant in their attitude toward Wang Yangming and his teachings. This tolerance was due to, on one hand, the academic open-mindedness of the Guangzhong school, and on the other, the Guanzhong scholars friendly contacts with Wang Yangming. By introducing his philosophy of the mind, Wang opened a new horizon for Ming Neo-Confucianism, making a contribution to correcting the fragmentary Zhu Xi studies of his time. Though most Guanzhong scholars followed Zhu Xi in their pursuit of Neo-Confucianism, they also made some criticisms and rectifications of Zhus doctrine. In this regard, they shared some common ground with Wang. However, Wangs theories of intuitive knowledge, extending knowledge, knowledge and action as one, and gongfu were troubled by some theoretical defects and drawbacks, and particularly, many later followers of Wang had a distorted understanding of his academic opinions. All these brought about an overall criticism within the middle Ming dynasty Confucians against Wang himself and his teachings. This was the historical background in which the Guanzhong scholars criticism against Wang was situated.

    Bibliography of Cited Translations

    Chan, Wing-tsit, trans. and comp. A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1963.

    Henke, Frederick Goodrich, trans. The Philosophy of Wang Yangming. London and Chicago: The Open Court Publishing Co., 1916.

    Legge, James, trans. Analects. http://ctext.org/analects, accessed May 12, 2020.

    Translated by Wang Xiaonong

    猜你喜歡
    樊遲關(guān)學(xué)顏淵
    解讀《論語》
    “關(guān)學(xué)”的精粹及其對(duì)后世的啟迪——張載思想的當(dāng)代價(jià)值研究
    張載關(guān)學(xué)暨關(guān)學(xué)文獻(xiàn)整理與研究學(xué)術(shù)會(huì)議在西安舉行
    張載關(guān)學(xué)暨關(guān)學(xué)文獻(xiàn)整理與研究學(xué)術(shù)會(huì)議在西安舉行
    國內(nèi)首家關(guān)學(xué)研究機(jī)構(gòu)在西北大學(xué)成立
    《論語》中的語境還原與文意理解
    《論語》中的語境還原與文意理解
    從《論語》中“子教樊遲”淺議如何引導(dǎo)學(xué)困生
    教師·中(2016年4期)2016-05-12 21:09:17
    顏淵之死
    是誰害了顏淵
    小說月刊(2008年5期)2008-05-30 10:36:06
    天堂av国产一区二区熟女人妻| 我的老师免费观看完整版| 亚洲精品,欧美精品| 长腿黑丝高跟| 中文乱码字字幕精品一区二区三区 | av在线天堂中文字幕| 亚洲国产精品成人久久小说| 大又大粗又爽又黄少妇毛片口| 一个人看的www免费观看视频| 久久99精品国语久久久| 在线观看美女被高潮喷水网站| 秋霞在线观看毛片| 97超碰精品成人国产| 精品人妻偷拍中文字幕| 九色成人免费人妻av| 亚洲国产最新在线播放| 直男gayav资源| 国产精品一区二区三区四区免费观看| 久久这里只有精品中国| 午夜老司机福利剧场| 蜜桃久久精品国产亚洲av| 人妻制服诱惑在线中文字幕| 3wmmmm亚洲av在线观看| 国产免费视频播放在线视频 | 久久精品国产亚洲av涩爱| 国产av在哪里看| 久久久久久国产a免费观看| 精品欧美国产一区二区三| 最近最新中文字幕大全电影3| 免费无遮挡裸体视频| 97人妻精品一区二区三区麻豆| 美女xxoo啪啪120秒动态图| 最近2019中文字幕mv第一页| 国产成人精品一,二区| 亚洲电影在线观看av| 日日撸夜夜添| 最近手机中文字幕大全| 亚洲三级黄色毛片| 午夜日本视频在线| 我要搜黄色片| 免费看日本二区| 尾随美女入室| 日本色播在线视频| 少妇猛男粗大的猛烈进出视频 | 亚洲欧美清纯卡通| 老女人水多毛片| 欧美区成人在线视频| 婷婷六月久久综合丁香| 毛片女人毛片| 啦啦啦韩国在线观看视频| 天堂中文最新版在线下载 | 国产极品精品免费视频能看的| 国产精品国产三级国产av玫瑰| 久久午夜福利片| 久久久久久久久久久丰满| 网址你懂的国产日韩在线| 欧美日韩精品成人综合77777| 69人妻影院| 久久精品国产99精品国产亚洲性色| 欧美人与善性xxx| av播播在线观看一区| av在线天堂中文字幕| 麻豆av噜噜一区二区三区| 亚洲无线观看免费| 亚洲成人精品中文字幕电影| 免费大片18禁| 女的被弄到高潮叫床怎么办| 夫妻性生交免费视频一级片| 亚洲国产精品专区欧美| 一区二区三区乱码不卡18| 国产在视频线在精品| 成人亚洲欧美一区二区av| 精品久久久久久电影网 | 纵有疾风起免费观看全集完整版 | 国产精品女同一区二区软件| 内地一区二区视频在线| 午夜福利在线观看免费完整高清在| 国产一区亚洲一区在线观看| 亚洲人与动物交配视频| 国产精品人妻久久久久久| 亚洲精品乱码久久久久久按摩| 国产一区二区亚洲精品在线观看| 日韩一区二区三区影片| 国内精品一区二区在线观看| 搡女人真爽免费视频火全软件| 毛片一级片免费看久久久久| 夜夜爽夜夜爽视频| 日产精品乱码卡一卡2卡三| 我要看日韩黄色一级片| 午夜福利成人在线免费观看| 精品国产一区二区三区久久久樱花 | 欧美成人午夜免费资源| h日本视频在线播放| 日本wwww免费看| 一区二区三区乱码不卡18| 日本一本二区三区精品| 91久久精品电影网| 国产黄色小视频在线观看| 午夜福利成人在线免费观看| 色网站视频免费| 99久久中文字幕三级久久日本| 午夜免费激情av| 国产成人a区在线观看| 国产爱豆传媒在线观看| 观看美女的网站| 亚洲人成网站在线播| 欧美日韩综合久久久久久| 日韩大片免费观看网站 | 一级黄色大片毛片| 高清av免费在线| 午夜激情欧美在线| 网址你懂的国产日韩在线| 我的女老师完整版在线观看| 久久人人爽人人片av| 精品少妇黑人巨大在线播放 | 免费观看精品视频网站| 少妇人妻一区二区三区视频| 亚洲精品影视一区二区三区av| 乱码一卡2卡4卡精品| 大话2 男鬼变身卡| 亚洲最大成人av| 久久久国产成人精品二区| 免费无遮挡裸体视频| 丰满人妻一区二区三区视频av| 国产淫片久久久久久久久| 免费av观看视频| 久久国产乱子免费精品| 午夜福利视频1000在线观看| 赤兔流量卡办理| 欧美日本亚洲视频在线播放| 一个人观看的视频www高清免费观看| 尤物成人国产欧美一区二区三区| 91午夜精品亚洲一区二区三区| 亚洲av一区综合| 蜜桃久久精品国产亚洲av| 亚洲电影在线观看av| 色哟哟·www| 成人鲁丝片一二三区免费| 三级经典国产精品| 久久久精品94久久精品| 内地一区二区视频在线| 成人毛片60女人毛片免费| 综合色av麻豆| 18禁动态无遮挡网站| 精品国产露脸久久av麻豆 | 岛国在线免费视频观看| 亚洲国产精品国产精品| 永久网站在线| 国产高清有码在线观看视频| 久久久精品大字幕| 亚洲真实伦在线观看| 岛国在线免费视频观看| 久久这里有精品视频免费| 欧美日本亚洲视频在线播放| 亚洲高清免费不卡视频| 欧美高清成人免费视频www| 国产不卡一卡二| 国内精品宾馆在线| 国内精品一区二区在线观看| 天堂√8在线中文| 麻豆乱淫一区二区| h日本视频在线播放| 亚洲av成人av| 国产91av在线免费观看| 日韩一本色道免费dvd| 成人午夜高清在线视频| 亚洲在线观看片| 人人妻人人澡欧美一区二区| 嫩草影院入口| 亚洲欧美成人精品一区二区| 一本—道久久a久久精品蜜桃钙片 精品乱码久久久久久99久播 | 亚洲av电影在线观看一区二区三区 | 女人十人毛片免费观看3o分钟| 日韩欧美国产在线观看| 日韩欧美精品v在线| 精品久久久久久久末码| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜添av毛片| 久久久久久久久久黄片| 免费看日本二区| av.在线天堂| 国产精品精品国产色婷婷| 精品99又大又爽又粗少妇毛片| 三级国产精品欧美在线观看| 亚洲欧美日韩卡通动漫| 小蜜桃在线观看免费完整版高清| 99热网站在线观看| 色视频www国产| 欧美日韩综合久久久久久| a级毛片免费高清观看在线播放| 中文字幕制服av| 国产免费一级a男人的天堂| 欧美性感艳星| 国产色婷婷99| 国产精品av视频在线免费观看| 亚洲欧美中文字幕日韩二区| 精品国产一区二区三区久久久樱花 | 亚洲av福利一区| 狠狠狠狠99中文字幕| 春色校园在线视频观看| 国产视频内射| 联通29元200g的流量卡| 国产精品国产高清国产av| 中文天堂在线官网| 99在线人妻在线中文字幕| 免费观看的影片在线观看| 九九爱精品视频在线观看| 伦理电影大哥的女人| 国产精品无大码| 免费大片18禁| 又爽又黄无遮挡网站| 久久久久免费精品人妻一区二区| 欧美又色又爽又黄视频| a级毛片免费高清观看在线播放| 精品人妻熟女av久视频| 国产免费又黄又爽又色| 波多野结衣高清无吗| 六月丁香七月| 在线播放无遮挡| 国产私拍福利视频在线观看| 久久久久久久国产电影| av播播在线观看一区| 亚洲最大成人手机在线| 亚洲经典国产精华液单| 日韩强制内射视频| 99热精品在线国产| 免费播放大片免费观看视频在线观看 | 日韩欧美国产在线观看| 内射极品少妇av片p| 亚洲av免费在线观看| 国产精品一二三区在线看| 国产精品久久久久久久电影| 91精品伊人久久大香线蕉| 久久这里有精品视频免费| 国产精品av视频在线免费观看| 最近的中文字幕免费完整| 一个人看的www免费观看视频| 久久久久久大精品| 国产成人精品一,二区| 欧美日韩精品成人综合77777| av女优亚洲男人天堂| 网址你懂的国产日韩在线| 综合色av麻豆| 国产精品电影一区二区三区| 七月丁香在线播放| 欧美成人午夜免费资源| 免费观看a级毛片全部| 国产人妻一区二区三区在| 黄色日韩在线| 搡老妇女老女人老熟妇| 国产伦理片在线播放av一区| 有码 亚洲区| 久久精品国产鲁丝片午夜精品| 2021天堂中文幕一二区在线观| 美女cb高潮喷水在线观看| 亚洲成av人片在线播放无| 最近最新中文字幕免费大全7| 免费看日本二区| 国产爱豆传媒在线观看| 国产精品嫩草影院av在线观看| 色综合色国产| 一夜夜www| 99久久精品一区二区三区| 日日撸夜夜添| 亚洲精品一区蜜桃| 久久精品夜夜夜夜夜久久蜜豆| 久久精品夜色国产| av在线蜜桃| 国产成人a∨麻豆精品| 中国美白少妇内射xxxbb| 国产成人91sexporn| 干丝袜人妻中文字幕| 美女脱内裤让男人舔精品视频| 搡老妇女老女人老熟妇| 91狼人影院| 精品午夜福利在线看| 一卡2卡三卡四卡精品乱码亚洲| 亚洲av中文av极速乱| 禁无遮挡网站| 小说图片视频综合网站| 国产成人a∨麻豆精品| 国产伦理片在线播放av一区| 国产精品爽爽va在线观看网站| 真实男女啪啪啪动态图| 日本与韩国留学比较| 国产精华一区二区三区| 亚洲成人av在线免费| 搡老妇女老女人老熟妇| 伦精品一区二区三区| 色哟哟·www| av在线老鸭窝| 搡女人真爽免费视频火全软件| 欧美丝袜亚洲另类| 男的添女的下面高潮视频| 午夜福利在线观看吧| 欧美97在线视频| 日韩中字成人| 如何舔出高潮| 亚洲国产精品sss在线观看| 三级毛片av免费| 欧美三级亚洲精品| 亚洲精品国产av成人精品| 女人久久www免费人成看片 | .国产精品久久| 免费大片18禁| 特级一级黄色大片| 深爱激情五月婷婷| 久久久欧美国产精品| 99久国产av精品国产电影| 国产精品乱码一区二三区的特点| 丰满乱子伦码专区| 免费一级毛片在线播放高清视频| 久久精品影院6| 丝袜喷水一区| 爱豆传媒免费全集在线观看| 亚洲天堂国产精品一区在线| 日韩制服骚丝袜av| 久久久久久久久久久丰满| 亚洲精品成人久久久久久| 久久久久性生活片| 久久99精品国语久久久| 成人av在线播放网站| 日本黄色视频三级网站网址| 男插女下体视频免费在线播放| 伊人久久精品亚洲午夜| 亚洲av福利一区| av线在线观看网站| 国产精品久久久久久精品电影| 如何舔出高潮| 国产不卡一卡二| 亚洲精品456在线播放app| 免费看a级黄色片| 日韩亚洲欧美综合| 两个人的视频大全免费| 亚洲欧美日韩高清专用| 中文天堂在线官网| 最近2019中文字幕mv第一页| 亚洲精品日韩在线中文字幕| 日韩一区二区三区影片| 日本与韩国留学比较| 免费在线观看成人毛片| 亚洲真实伦在线观看| 狂野欧美白嫩少妇大欣赏| 人妻夜夜爽99麻豆av| 男人的好看免费观看在线视频| 国产老妇女一区| 一个人观看的视频www高清免费观看| 久久鲁丝午夜福利片| 日本免费a在线| 中国美白少妇内射xxxbb| 狂野欧美激情性xxxx在线观看| 国产精品野战在线观看| 久久精品综合一区二区三区| 免费av观看视频| 男女国产视频网站| 亚洲无线观看免费| 久久99热这里只频精品6学生 | 97在线视频观看| 啦啦啦韩国在线观看视频| 亚洲av成人av| 午夜视频国产福利| 日韩强制内射视频| 国产成人一区二区在线| 免费观看人在逋| 国产精品99久久久久久久久| 校园人妻丝袜中文字幕| 精品酒店卫生间| 欧美激情在线99| 天天一区二区日本电影三级| 91精品伊人久久大香线蕉| 国产精品.久久久| 国产精品久久久久久av不卡| 久久久久久久久久久免费av| 免费搜索国产男女视频| 国产精品1区2区在线观看.| 18禁在线无遮挡免费观看视频| 网址你懂的国产日韩在线| 欧美成人a在线观看| 黄色日韩在线| 免费观看的影片在线观看| 午夜福利在线观看免费完整高清在| 禁无遮挡网站| ponron亚洲| 51国产日韩欧美| 久久久亚洲精品成人影院| 欧美xxxx性猛交bbbb| 在线观看av片永久免费下载| 麻豆乱淫一区二区| 成人三级黄色视频| 免费黄网站久久成人精品| 亚洲av成人精品一二三区| 色尼玛亚洲综合影院| 日日撸夜夜添| 国产探花在线观看一区二区| 国产精品爽爽va在线观看网站| 久久亚洲国产成人精品v| 久久综合国产亚洲精品| 欧美激情久久久久久爽电影| 一区二区三区免费毛片| 精品熟女少妇av免费看| 国产人妻一区二区三区在| 日韩一本色道免费dvd| 秋霞在线观看毛片| 免费观看a级毛片全部| 精品99又大又爽又粗少妇毛片| 亚洲欧美成人综合另类久久久 | 久久久久久久午夜电影| 91狼人影院| 一区二区三区四区激情视频| 亚洲成人av在线免费| 久久国内精品自在自线图片| 国产亚洲av嫩草精品影院| 免费观看在线日韩| 亚洲人与动物交配视频| 亚洲国产精品sss在线观看| 欧美极品一区二区三区四区| 亚洲综合色惰| 国产精品电影一区二区三区| 99九九线精品视频在线观看视频| 国产毛片a区久久久久| 国产精品久久视频播放| 日本黄大片高清| av女优亚洲男人天堂| 男人舔奶头视频| 色视频www国产| 婷婷色综合大香蕉| 国产大屁股一区二区在线视频| 亚洲国产欧洲综合997久久,| 午夜视频国产福利| 免费观看性生交大片5| 国产精品1区2区在线观看.| 最近手机中文字幕大全| 男女啪啪激烈高潮av片| 蜜桃亚洲精品一区二区三区| 亚洲怡红院男人天堂| 国产一区有黄有色的免费视频 | 亚洲av一区综合| 欧美激情久久久久久爽电影| 日本一二三区视频观看| 男人舔奶头视频| 亚洲精品456在线播放app| 搡女人真爽免费视频火全软件| 国产又黄又爽又无遮挡在线| 欧美一区二区国产精品久久精品| 日韩国内少妇激情av| 亚洲精品影视一区二区三区av| 亚洲电影在线观看av| 水蜜桃什么品种好| 91aial.com中文字幕在线观看| 色噜噜av男人的天堂激情| 成人鲁丝片一二三区免费| 成人国产麻豆网| 99热这里只有是精品50| 国产精品爽爽va在线观看网站| 不卡视频在线观看欧美| 一区二区三区免费毛片| 午夜福利高清视频| 如何舔出高潮| 黑人高潮一二区| 午夜免费男女啪啪视频观看| 69av精品久久久久久| 人体艺术视频欧美日本| 亚洲人与动物交配视频| 色噜噜av男人的天堂激情| av在线老鸭窝| 听说在线观看完整版免费高清| 少妇高潮的动态图| 日韩亚洲欧美综合| av播播在线观看一区| 精品99又大又爽又粗少妇毛片| 热99在线观看视频| 啦啦啦韩国在线观看视频| 偷拍熟女少妇极品色| 国产白丝娇喘喷水9色精品| 久久久久九九精品影院| 久久久午夜欧美精品| 亚洲av电影不卡..在线观看| 国产高清视频在线观看网站| 亚洲性久久影院| 亚洲婷婷狠狠爱综合网| 国产精品综合久久久久久久免费| 国产v大片淫在线免费观看| 久久久久久久久大av| 国产精品电影一区二区三区| 最近中文字幕高清免费大全6| 老司机影院毛片| 乱系列少妇在线播放| 亚洲精品日韩av片在线观看| 最近最新中文字幕大全电影3| a级毛片免费高清观看在线播放| 久久鲁丝午夜福利片| 日本一二三区视频观看| 免费看a级黄色片| 色尼玛亚洲综合影院| 精品久久久久久久久av| 亚洲最大成人中文| 亚洲四区av| 亚洲av中文av极速乱| 精品久久久久久成人av| 国产成人福利小说| 黄色配什么色好看| 中文乱码字字幕精品一区二区三区 | 久久精品国产自在天天线| 观看免费一级毛片| 一级二级三级毛片免费看| 夫妻性生交免费视频一级片| 51国产日韩欧美| 男女下面进入的视频免费午夜| 国产色爽女视频免费观看| 久久久精品欧美日韩精品| 国产黄片美女视频| 国产美女午夜福利| 亚洲欧美成人综合另类久久久 | 岛国在线免费视频观看| 我的老师免费观看完整版| 婷婷色av中文字幕| 一本—道久久a久久精品蜜桃钙片 精品乱码久久久久久99久播 | 中文字幕精品亚洲无线码一区| 最新中文字幕久久久久| 国产探花在线观看一区二区| 久久99热这里只频精品6学生 | 亚洲婷婷狠狠爱综合网| 日韩av在线免费看完整版不卡| 欧美另类亚洲清纯唯美| 精品久久国产蜜桃| 成年版毛片免费区| 国产黄色视频一区二区在线观看 | 久久久精品大字幕| 久久99热这里只频精品6学生 | 国模一区二区三区四区视频| 神马国产精品三级电影在线观看| 亚洲国产精品国产精品| 嫩草影院精品99| 人体艺术视频欧美日本| 久久99热6这里只有精品| 久久久久久久久大av| 国产亚洲精品av在线| 性色avwww在线观看| av在线观看视频网站免费| 亚洲天堂国产精品一区在线| 欧美性感艳星| 永久网站在线| 国产v大片淫在线免费观看| 长腿黑丝高跟| 国产精品.久久久| 亚洲欧美一区二区三区国产| 九九久久精品国产亚洲av麻豆| 免费一级毛片在线播放高清视频| 嫩草影院入口| 国产av在哪里看| 久久人妻av系列| 少妇裸体淫交视频免费看高清| 亚洲电影在线观看av| 婷婷色av中文字幕| 久久人人爽人人爽人人片va| 99久久九九国产精品国产免费| 能在线免费观看的黄片| 久久99热这里只有精品18| 中文字幕av在线有码专区| 一边摸一边抽搐一进一小说| 中文欧美无线码| 国产日韩欧美在线精品| 岛国在线免费视频观看| 男女啪啪激烈高潮av片| 天堂影院成人在线观看| 99九九线精品视频在线观看视频| 亚洲第一区二区三区不卡| 如何舔出高潮| 97在线视频观看| 精品国产一区二区三区久久久樱花 | 欧美+日韩+精品| 最近手机中文字幕大全| 美女大奶头视频| 一级毛片aaaaaa免费看小| 嫩草影院入口| 欧美日本亚洲视频在线播放| 黄色欧美视频在线观看| 一个人免费在线观看电影| 我的老师免费观看完整版| 蜜桃久久精品国产亚洲av| 狂野欧美激情性xxxx在线观看| 熟女电影av网| 欧美成人免费av一区二区三区| 国产黄a三级三级三级人| 久久久久久久久久久免费av| 久久久久性生活片| 亚洲18禁久久av| 看十八女毛片水多多多| 国产乱来视频区| 精品午夜福利在线看| 国产精品.久久久| 能在线免费观看的黄片| 少妇人妻一区二区三区视频| 级片在线观看| 国产一区二区亚洲精品在线观看| 亚洲精华国产精华液的使用体验| 久久99热这里只频精品6学生 | 国产不卡一卡二| 又爽又黄a免费视频| 国产精品,欧美在线| 中文字幕久久专区| 国产精品爽爽va在线观看网站| 国产老妇女一区| 国产精品久久久久久久久免| 色综合站精品国产| 国产av码专区亚洲av| 亚洲av不卡在线观看| 国产亚洲最大av| 寂寞人妻少妇视频99o| 日本三级黄在线观看| 综合色丁香网| 日韩人妻高清精品专区| 国产高清三级在线| 日韩av在线大香蕉| 2022亚洲国产成人精品| 成人综合一区亚洲|