• <tr id="yyy80"></tr>
  • <sup id="yyy80"></sup>
  • <tfoot id="yyy80"><noscript id="yyy80"></noscript></tfoot>
  • 99热精品在线国产_美女午夜性视频免费_国产精品国产高清国产av_av欧美777_自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇_亚洲熟女精品中文字幕_www日本黄色视频网_国产精品野战在线观看 ?

    The Rationality Dialogy Between Economics and Psychology

    2016-03-28 08:14:33
    Contemporary Social Sciences 2016年1期

    The Rationality Dialogy Between Economics and Psychology

    Jing Qian*

    Economics and psychology take distinct approaches to predicting and formalizing human behavior. Economics focuses on the normative view of rationality, while psychology emphasizes the descriptive nature of rationality. This article reviews models of rationality related to understanding human decision making, including notions of complete rationality, bounded rationality, and ecological rationality. By examining the aims and functions of such rationality models, the author wishes to draw attention to the utility of ecological rationality and adaptive rationality approaches in a unified theoretical model for understanding human rationality. The ecological rationality approach evaluates not only by performance, but more importantly by how well the behavior fits the individual' s environment. The adaptive rationality approach completes this model by additionally incorporating changes to the environment.

    Rationality debate; Bounded rationality; Ecological rationality; Adaptive Rationality

    Economics and psychology, two important branches of social sciences, take distinct approaches to predicting and formalizing human behavior. As a normative science, economics is mostly concerned with issues of how people should make optimal decisions. Working from a different angle, psychology is mainly concerned with describing how decisions are made. Various types of work have been done at the interface between psychology and economics, including studies of bounded rationality (Gigerenzer& Selten, 2003, 2001; Simon, 1955); heuristics and biases in decision-making (Kahneman&Tversky,1996; Tversky&Kahneman, 1975), experimental economics (e.g, Hertwig, 1998; Starmer, 1999), and behavioral economics (e.g., Camerer, Loewenstein, & Rabin, 2003; Rabin, 1998).

    In this article, I will review the debate and dialog about rationality among economists and psychologists. First, a historical review of the notion of rationality in economics will show that the idea of rationality in economics is closely related to the notion of the "economic man", whose capability in making decisions is beyond the actual capability of the human mind. Second, we will review criticisms of the classic economic view of rationality, represented by the work of three different research groups: the heuristics and biases program of Kahneman, Tversky, and others (Gilovich, Griffin, &Kahneman, 2002), the notion of bounded rationality advocated by Herbert Simon (1955; 1956; 1982), and the more recent view of adaptive rationality proposed by Anderson (1990), Gigerenzer (2000), and Oaksford and Chater (1998). The differing approaches of bounded rationality and adaptive rationality share the assumption that many aspects of human behavior can be understood as adaptively rational for an organism with limited resources in a structured environment. It is concluded that the adaptive rationality approach, and in particular the need to focus on the structure of the environment is of vital importance to understanding behavior.

    1. The Rationality Debate

    Rationality is a broad concept that typically encompasses the appropriate use of logic as well as "uncertain but sensible arguments" based on probability, expectation, personal experience and the like. The rationality debates among economists and psychologists is mainly constituted of discussions about complete (unbounded) rationality and bounded rationality, but also includes debate regarding whether observed deviations from the conventional normative standards should be interpreted as "adaptive rationality" or "irrational biases". The view of rationality in economics is undergoing some changes as a result of these debates.

    2. Rationality in Economics

    The assumption of rationality lies at the heart of modern economic theory. The concept of rationality in economics, first introduced by Adam Smith (1776), is now generally viewed as the choice of optimal means to achieve a given end (Gerrard, 1993). In one key textbook of microeconomics (Frank, 2002), being rational is defined in terms of making choices if and only if the benefits exceed the costs of the choice. This notion of rationality is based on the four assumptions of Neoclassical Economics, personified in the concept homo economicus (economic man)-a decision maker who incorporates the characteristics of self-interest, omniscience (having complete information), conscious deliberation (mental calculation of an optimized "as if" equivalent), and representativeness (i.e., homo economicus is representative of all decision makers). The assumption of rationality in normative economics amounts to the claim that agents should optimize. In positive economics, where the focus is on developing and testing economic theories, the premise of rationality is the hypothesis of maintained consistency (Gerrard, 1993). The concept of rationality through the development of Economics has however, changed over time, and the following summary aims to review the different notions of rationality that have accompanied the development of economic theories.

    The concept of rationality as it appeared in The Wealth of Nations (Smith, 1776) was viewedin terms of the standards of economic production and trade. It implied that when people see a clear advantage in a particular course of action, they will act upon it. This notion of rationality is the rationality of everyday common sense. The logic behind Smith' s work is that when every individual pursues solely his/her selfish goals, the market will reach its maximum efficiency. This assumption of rationality does not depend on an elaborate calculus of utility or assume any consistency in the factors that are taken into consideration when moving from one choice situation to another (Simon, 1997; Smith, 1937).

    In Alfred Marshall' s Principles of Economics (1920), a wider notion of rationality was developed to incorporate not only the study of wealth, but also the study of the economic agent. Rationality requires the ability to forecast the future and shape one' s course with reference to distant aims. The emphasis is placed upon deliberation in decision making, which involves marginal analysis (Book IV) and maximization of utility (Book III). From this point on, neoclassical economics was established, and economics became more mathematical in nature. The assumption of rationality approximated the assumption of optimality in choices and decisions. Marshall' s contemporary neoclassical economists—William Stanley Jevon (1871), Carl Menger (1871), and Leon Walras (1954) proclaimed that rationality is exemplified by utility maximization in a general equilibrium framework.

    With John Maynard Keynes' General Theory of Employment (1936), the concept of rationality departed from the key assumptions of the neoclassical framework. The author claimed that the neo-classical system represented "the way in which we should like our Economy to behave…But to assume that it actually does so is to assume our difficulties away" (p.34). He asserted that people do not have complete rationality. It was lapses from rationality of these sorts that brought about departures from a full employment of resources, and these lapses could be remedied by appropriate governmental policies. In The General Theory, Keynes comments:

    There is the instability due to the characteristic of human nature that a large proportion of our positive activities depend on spontaneous optimism rather than on a mathematical expectation, whether moral or hedonistic or economic…Most, probably, of our decisions to do something positive, the full consequences of which will be drawn out over many days to come, can only be taken as a result of animal spirits-of spontaneous urge to action rather than inaction, and not as the outcome of a weighted average of quantitative benefits multiplied by quantitative probabilities (p.161-162).

    Keynes pointed out the unrealistic nature of the rationality assumption in mainstream economics, but this line of thought was not followed by others. In Essays in Positive Economics (1953), Milton Friedman returned to the Neo-classical version of rationality. Acknowledging the unrealistic assumption underlying economic models—that decision makers have to be "Laplacean Demons" to be able to make optimization calculations—he instead proposed that economic agents make decisions "as if" they were applying complicated optimizations. He used examples like the Newtonian physical laws regarding free fall objects, biological phenomena concerning the density distributions of trees, and the manner pool players strike the ball as analogies for how economic agents "appear to" make decisions "as if" they were following strategies derived from precise optimal calculations:

    It is only a short step from these examples to the economic hypothesis that under a wide range of circumstances individual firms behave as if they were seeking rationally to maximize their expected returns, and had full knowledge of the data needed to succeed in this attempt; as if, that is, they knew the relevant cost and demand functions, calculated marginal cost and marginal revenue from all actions open to them, and pushed each line of action to the point at which the relevant marginal cost and marginal revenue were equal. (p.21).

    Even though the assumption that an economic agent employs mathematical optimization in making every decision is clearly unrealistic, mainstream economists do accept that agents behave "as if" they are using optimization. Friedman' s view of rationality became very popular among economists, who took the "as if" rational model as a useful approximation of human behavior.

    The modern notion of rationality in Decision Theory (or Rational Choice Theory) is based on Savage' s formalization of Expected Utility Theory (1954), which states that the decision maker chooses between risky or uncertain prospects by comparing their expected utility values. Expected utility was formalized in the multiplicative combination of outcome utility values and their respective probabilities. To be rational in decisionmaking under risk one must have complete and transitive preferences. In the domain of decisionmaking under uncertainty, von Neumann-Morgenstern Theory (VNMT) states that being rational means having preferences that are also independent. These assumptions of consistency in preferences allow expected utilities from all alternatives to be calculated and compared, and allow a choice to be made for the most preferred option using utility maximization. In order to have consistent preferences, a decision maker is assumed to have all information about all the options, their probability of occurrence (either from a probability distribution in the case of decision under risk, or subjective probability in the case of decision under uncertainty), and to have the time and ability to weigh every choice against every other choice.

    In general, the approaches reviewed above share a concept of rationality developed within economics bound by the idealistic, logical, deductive, and normative qualities of homo economicus. This notion of rationality is "useful in generating solutions to theoretical problems, but it demands much of human behavior—much more in fact than it can deliver" (Arthur, 1994, p.406). Criticisms about the general assumptions that this "economic man" represents in economics have come mainly from three areas. The following sections review these criticisms.

    3. Criticisms of Unbounded Rationality

    Around the same time Expected Utility Theory (EUT) became the dominant model of individual behavior in economics literature, and a large body of evidence was accumulating that human behavior deviates systematically from the idealized behavior assumed by economists who believe decision makers maximize expected utility.

    3.1 Heuristics and Biases

    This evidence (Gilovich, Griffin, &Kahneman, 2002; Kahneman, Slovic, &Tversky, 1982), collectively dubbed Kahneman and Tversky' s Heuristics and Biases program, used a broad array of problems to demonstrate experimentally that, under quite ordinary circumstances,people reason and make decisions in ways that systematically deviate from what would be predicted according to the basic rules of logic and probability theory. Specifically, people do not have consistent preferences, and their preferences may vary in accordance with contextual settings or mental representations. Such phenomena as the endowment effect (Kahneman, Knetsch, &Thaler, 1991), loss aversion (ibid.), status quo bias (ibid.), framing effects (Tversky&Kahneman, 1986), and preference reversals (Slovic& Lichtenstein, 1983) are well-established anomalies that violate the assumption of consistency in Expected Utility Theory. On the basis of a series of studies, Tversky and Kahneman (1974) concluded that, "people rely on a limited number of heuristic principles which reduce the complex tasks of assessing probabilities and predicting values to simpler judgemental operations. In general, these heuristics are quite useful, but sometimes lead to severe and systematic errors" (p.1124).

    The Heuristics and Biases program showed that as people employ a handful of heuristics when making decisions, deviations from normative models are systematic and predictable. Kahneman and Tversky (1973) argued that human choices are not consistent and transitive, as they would be if a utility function existed. Their studies invalidate the justification of the "as if" approximation in normative economic models, and call for alternative models to be proposed.

    Prospect Theory (Kahneman&Tversky, 1979) offered an alternative framework for judgment and choice under risk. According to Prospect Theory, the decision process consists of the editing phase and the evaluation phase. In the editing phase, prospects are coded in terms of gains and losses, combining common features and segregating riskless components. The core of Prospect Theory, however, lies in the evaluation phase. A reference-dependent value function together with a probability weighting function is used to transform outcomes and probabilities into subjective utility and decision weights. The value function is concave for gains and convex for losses. The weighting function assumes the overweighting of small probabilities and underweighting of large probabilities typical of subjective judgments. The outcomes of these two functions are multiplied in a similar fashion to calculations used in EUT, and preferences are predicted by comparing the values of these outputs. Prospect Theory provided an account of a range of empirical observations on the differential weighting of gains and losses, as well as high and low probabilities; thus, its formulation solved several violations of Subjective Expected Utility Theory (SEU). This theory provides a good descriptive account of decision making under risk, but remains only a descriptive account, because it does not answer why people employ such heuristics.

    Similar to work by Evans and Over (1996) that marked a distinction between bounded and unbounded rationality types, Kahneman (2003) emphasized a distinction between two types of mental processes: those that are part of the intuitive automatic system (which are error-prone), and those that are part of the serial effortful deductive system that follows strict rules.

    By treating decision heuristics as biases, the evident conclusion is that humans are not rational because they systematically display reasoning errors and inconsistency in preferences relative to normative standards. As with optical illusions, human are easily susceptible to cognitive illusions that cannot be reconciled (Kahneman, 1996). The Heuristics and Biases program preserved the normative standards of Neo-classical Economics while developing the view that the human mind normally operates using heuristics. This extremeconclusion from the heuristics and biases programthat deviations from SEU theory are biased and irrational-has met with severe criticism from several researchers. Rather than detailing these numerous criticisms, I will focus instead on the alternative approach offered by bounded rationality.

    3.2 Bounded Rationality

    In an attempt to understand complex human decision making, Herbert Simon (1955, 1979, 1982, 1992, 1997a) was the first to chart both how and why cognitive reality departs from the formalized ideal decision environment assumed by normative theories of Economics. As Simon (1975) noted:

    The capacity of the human mind for formulation and solving complex problems is very small compared with the size of the problems whose solution is required for objectively rational behavior in the real worldor even for a reasonable approximation of such objective rationality (p.198).

    This fundamental limitation on human information processing gives rise, according to Simon, to satisficing behavior-the tendency to settle for satisfactory, rather than optimal, courses of action. In terms of bounded rationality, people satisfice with respect to their aspiration level instead of optimizing with respect to all information about the world.

    "One requirement of optimization not shared by satisficing is that all alternatives must be measurable in terms of a common utility function" (Simon, 1986, p.210). Simon (1956; 1979) pointed out that blocks of an organism' s time can be allocated to activities related to individual needs (separate means-ends chains) without creating any problem of overall allocation or coordination, or the need for any general utility function.

    Simon (1983) described Subjective Expected Utility Theory as "a beautiful object deserving a prominent place in Plato' s heaven of ideas" (p.13), but pointed out several ways in which realworld decision making falls a long way short of this ideal. Whereas SEU assumes that decision makers have an undisturbed view of all possible scenarios of action, real human decision-making is almost invariably focused upon specific matters. The former theory requires that the decision maker comprehend the entire range of possible alternatives, but decision makers are most likely to contemplate only a few of the available alternatives (Fischhoff, Slovic, & Lichtenstein, 1978). Human decision-making is constrained by its "keyhole" view of the problem space-what Simon (1975) has coined "bounded rationality".

    The bounds of rationality are dictated by the complexity of the world in which we live: the incompleteness and inadequacy of human knowledge, the inconsistencies of individual preference and belief, the conflicts of value among people and groups of people, and the inadequacy of the computations we can carry out, even with the aid of the most powerful computers (see Simon, 1956).

    In contrast with the assumptions of an economic man, Herbert Simon proposed a model of a thinking man, who makes decisions by "satisficing" rather than "maximizing". Simon (1979) emphasized the following qualities of a thinking man:

    Thinking Man is capable of expressing his cognitive skills in a wide range of task domains: learning and remembering, problem solving, inducing rules and attaining concepts, perceiving and recognizing stimuli, understanding natural language, and others. An information-processing model of Thinking Man must contain components capable of humanly intelligent behavior in each of these domains; and, as these models are created, they must gradually be merged into a coherent whole. (p.10).

    This account of bounded rationality that Thinking Man is equipped with is more closely related to psychological theories of perception, memory, learning and cognition. It calls for theories that address not only the cognitive mechanism of the decision maker who has limited time and knowledge, but also the structure of the environment to which the decision maker adapts. In Simon' s (1956) terms, "Human rational behavior is shaped by a scissors whose two blades are the structure of task environments and the computational capabilities of the actor." (p.129). Thus, one emphasis of the bounded rationality approach is the role of the decision environment. Recent accounts of adaptive rationality focus particularly on this aspect of rationality and evaluate rational behavior in light of the structure of the environment, ecological as well as contextual.

    3.3 Adaptive Rationality

    The concept of adaptive rationality, or ecological rationality, is related to the notion of bounded rationality. Particularly, great emphasis is placed upon the evaluation of human behavior in terms of its success in its natural environment rather than against normative standards. The central ideal behind adaptive rationality is that people use heuristics to solve everyday problems; and human memory and reasoning, which are evolved to facilitate the use of these heuristics, are adaptive and successful within a representative natural environment, even though sometimes these heuristics produce behaviors that are discordant with the laws of logic, probability theory, expected utility theory, and rational choice maxims. As Cosmides and Tooby (1994) pointed out, "Forms follow function: the properties of an evolved mechanism reflect the structure of the task it evolved to solve." (p.328). These heuristics are "smart" because they exploit the structure of the environment, they dispense with optimization and, for the most part, with calculations of probabilities and utilities. The fact that such heuristics do not fit into the framework of decision theory, leads to the question of whether traditional normative standards should be used to evaluate human rationality.

    In particular, Gerd Gigerenzer and colleagues (e.g. Simple Heuristics that Make us Smart, 1999b; Adaptive Thinking, 2000; Bounded Rationality, 2000) established research programs investigating the adaptive nature of human behavior, with a focus on the use of fast and frugal heuristics. Gigerenzer (2000) compared the human brain to an "adaptive toolbox", which is a repertoire of such heuristics. Their central argument is that "fast and frugal" strategies can perform as well as full optimization if not more, but they operate at a much lower cost cognitively.

    Fast and frugal heuristics such as the recognition heuristic and the "take-the-best" strategy are extremely effective in tasks like these, when the distribution of information in the environment is skewed, and the cognitive resources of the decision makers are limited. Gigerenzer and Goldstein (1996) argued that the mere success of human inferential ability in evolutionary terms is "an existence proof" for adaptive rationality, and such rationality need not be judged in terms of rational norms. They further challenged the validity of classical rationality as the standard for measuring rationality, and suggested that rationality should instead be measured by itssuccess in solving ecologically relevant problems.

    Chater, Oaksford, Nakisa, and Redington (2003) examined the viability of fast and frugal heuristics, and argued that the adaptive rationality approach could be consistent with classical rationality assumptions (such as probability theory and decision theory). They further assessed why fast and frugal heuristics are rational heuristics using the rational analysis method (Anderson, 1990). Evaluating the take-the-best heuristic (TTB) against the normative criteria, Chater et al. found that TTB performs impressively-especially in a frugal information environment-compared with other standard algorithms such as exemplarbased models (e.g., Nosofsky, 1990), connectionist networks (Rumelhart& McClelland, 1986), and decision trees (Quinlan, 1993). TTB is also impressive because it represents a process that is comparable to human performance. However, detailed analysis revealed that, though the TTB heuristic is fast and frugal, in some cases other algorithms are just as cognitively plausible.

    Payne, Bettman, and Johnson (1993) showed that fast and frugal heuristics are among a continuum of strategies that people employ daily. These heuristics are seen as applicable to a wide range of reasoning and judgement tasks (see Czerlinski, Gigerenzer, & Goldstein, 1999; Dhame& Ayton, 2001 for some interesting examples). Fast and frugal heuristics like TTB thrive in a decision environment where information is scarce and time is pressing. But given enough time and resources, people may not necessarily choose fast and frugal heuristics. Oppenheimer (2003) questioned the reason why the recognition heuristic, which is fundamental in the adaptive toolbox, succeeded. He suggested that its success may be attributed to people using knowledge associated with the non-compensatory cue of recognition rather than pure recognition. In the city size example, Oppenheimer hypothesizes that the recognition heuristic works because of people' s knowledge that the known cities are large. To test his hypothesis, he used local cities that are recognized but known to be small, and fictional cities for which participants could have no recognition. He found that local cities that people recognized were chosen as the smaller city on average, contrary to Gigerenzer and Goldstein' s finding, if taken at face value. Oppenheimer' s finding highlights the importance of the ecological validity of cues, and that the structure of the environment where information is retrieved may determine both the choice of heuristics and their success rate.

    Our memory system is one aspect of adaptive cognition that is optimized to the structure of the environment (Anderson &Schooler, 1991). The rate of forgetting an item in memory is optimized to the likelihood of encountering that item in the world. A rational analysis of information encoding in memory reveals that forgetting is adaptive, because it reflects the pattern with which certain information appears and reappears in the environment (Schooler&Hertwig, 2005).

    Oaksford and Chater (1998) reviewed the adaptableness of human behavior in light of the structure of the task environment. Aspects of adaptive cognition including categorization, information searching, and selecting evidence in reasoning may all be viewed as optimizing the amount of information gained at a fixed cost. The rational analysis approach to cognition can be seen as both descriptive and normative, because its hypotheses can be tested against empirical data. It can explain both how the mind works and why it is successful. This direction of research is different to that of deductive Neo-classical rationality in the a priori assumptions it holds. Rational analysis holds the assumption that accounts of the mindmust not only be both normatively justified, but also descriptively adequate.

    4. Conclusion

    The important differences in conceptualizations of rationality rest on a fundamental distinction: in economics, rationality is viewed in terms of the choices it produces; in the other social sciences, it is viewed in terms of the processes it employs (Simon, 1976, 1982, 1997).

    To be rational from the point of view of economics, with its manifestation of modern decision theory and probability theory, is to be deductive, logical, and consistent. When evaluating human behavior against these standards, systematic deviations from normative answers are often observed (as revealed by the heuristic and biases program). The heuristics and biases program treated these deviations as human biases, and suggested modifications to existing rational models (such as Expected Utility Theory) to incorporate these biases. In contrast to this, Gigerenzer (1996) argued that the norms for evaluating reasoning and decisions have been too narrowly drawn, and the type of reasoning task used to evaluate human rationality is devoid of context and content (Hertwig, Ortmann, &Gigerenzer, 1997). It is not irrational to make such errors, as people are adaptive thinkers who draw inferences from the statistical world where inductive information is valuable (e.g. Gigerenzer& Goldstein, 1996; Oaksford&Chater, 1994). Recent work has shifted the focus to notions of bounded and adaptive rationality, which aim to explain why it is that people use heuristics. Crucial to the shift is the emphasis on the structure of the environment. In a world of uncertainties, rational judgement will largely depend on making correct inference about the information distribution of the environment.

    [1] Anderson, J. R. The adaptive character of thought [M]. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. 1990.

    [2] Anderson, J. R., &Schooler, L. J. Refections of the environment in memory[J]. Psychological Science, 1991 (2), 396-408.

    [3] Arthur, W. B. Inductive reasoning and bounded rationality [J].American Economic Review, 1994(84), 406-411.

    [4] Camerer, C. F., Loewenstein, G., & Rabin, M. (Eds.). Advances in behavioral economics. [M]. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. 2003.

    [5] Chater, N., Oaksford, M., Nakisa, R. &Redington, M. (). Fast, frugal and rational: How rational norms explain behavior[J]. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 2003(90) 63-86.

    [6] Cosmides, L., &Tooby, J. (). Beyond intuition and instinct blindness: Towards an evolutionary rigorous cognitive science[J]. Cognition.1994(50) 41-77.

    [7] Czerlinski, J., Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. G. (). How good are simple heuristics? In G. Gigerenzer, P. M. Todd & The ABC Group (Eds.), Simple heuristics that make us smart[M]. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. 1999: 97-118

    [8] Dhami, M. K., & Ayton, P. Bailing and jailing the fast and frugal way[J].Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 2001(14) 141-168. [9]Evans, J. S. B. T., & Over, D. E. Rationality and reasoning[M]. Hove, Sussex: Psychology Press. 1996

    [10]Fischhoff, B Slovic, P., & Lichtenstein, S. Fault trees: Sensitivity of estimated failure probabilities to problem representation [J]. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 1978(4) 330-334.

    [11]Frank, R.H. Microeconomics and behavior (5th ed.)[M]. New York: McGraw-Hill. 2003

    [12]Friedman, M. The methodology of positive economics. In M. Friedman (Ed.), Essays on positive economics. [M]. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 1953.

    [13]Gerrard, B. The economics of rationality. [M]. London, Routledge. 1993

    [14]Gigerenzer, G. On narrow norms and vague heuristics: A reply to Kahneman and Tversky. [J]. Psychological Review, 1996.103, 592-596.

    [15]Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. G. Reasoning the fast and frugal way: Models of bounded rationality[J]. Psychological Review, 1996(103), 650-669.

    [16]Gigerenzer, G. Adaptive thinking: Rationality in the real world. [M]. London: Oxford University Press. 2000

    [17]Gigerenzer, G., &Selten, R. (). Bounded rationality: The adaptive tool box[J]. Psychology and Marketing, 2003(20), 87-92.

    [18]Gilovich, T., Griffn, D., &Kahneman, D. (Eds.). Heuristics and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment[M]. New York: Cambridge University Press. 2002

    [19]Hertwig, R. Psychology, experimental economics and the question of what good experimentation is / psychologie, experiment elleokonomie und die frage, was gutes experimentierenist. Zeitschrift fur [J].Experimentelle Psychologie, 1998(45) 2-19.

    [20]Hertwig, R., Ortmann, A., &Gigerenzer, G. Deductive competence: A desert devoid of content and context[J]. Current Psychology of Cognition, 1997(16) 102-107.

    [21]Jevons, W. S. The theory of political economy [M]. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1871[1970].

    [22]Kahneman, D. A perspective on judgment and choice: Mapping bounded rationality [J]. American Psychologist, 2003(58) 697-720.

    [23]Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J. L., &Thaler, R. H. The endowment effect, loss aversion, and the status quo bias[J]. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 1991(5) 193-206.

    [24]Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., &Tversky, A. (Eds.). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases[M]. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. 1982.

    [25]Kahneman, D., &Tversky, A. Prospect theory: An analysis of decisions under risk[J]. Econometrica, 1979(47) 263-291.

    [26]Kahneman, D., &Tversky, A. On the reality of cognitive illusions[J]. Psychological Review, 1996(103) 582-591.

    [27]Kahneman, D., &Tversky, A. (Eds.). Choices, values, and frames [M]. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. 2000.

    [28]Katz, M. L., & Rosen, H. S. (1998) Microeconomics (3rd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.

    [29]Keynes, J. M. The general theory of employment, interest and money[M].London: MacMillan. 1936.

    [30]Marshall, A. Principles of economics (8th ed.). [M]. New York: Macmillan. 1920.

    [31]Menger, C. Principles of Economics. Institute for Humane Studies Series in Economic Theory, 1871[1994].

    [32]Mosteller, F., &Nogee, P. An experimental measurement of utility[J]. Journal of Political Economy, 1951(54) 371-404.

    [33]Nosofsky, R. M. Relations between exemplar similarity and likelihood models of classifcation[J]. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 1990(34), 393–418.

    [34]Oaksford, M., &Chater, N. A rational analysis of the selection task as optimal data selection[J]. Psychological Review, 1994 (101), 608-631.

    [35]Oaksford, M., &Chater, N. (Eds.). Rational models of cognition. [M]. New York: Oxford University Press (1998).

    [36]Oppenheimer, D. M. Not so fast and not so frugal!: Rethinking the Recognition Heuristic. [J]. Cognition, 2003(90), B1-B9.

    [37]Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R., & Johnson, E. J. The adaptive decision maker. [M]. New York: Cambridge University Press. 1993.

    [38]Quinlan, J. R. C4.5: Programs for Machine Learning [M].Morgan Kaufmann, Los Altos. 1993.

    [39]Rabin, M. Psychology and economics. [J]. Journal of Economic Literature, 1998(36) 11-46.

    [40]Rumelhart, D. E., McClelland, J. L., & The PDP Research Group Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructures of cognition .1986 (Vols. 1 & 2).

    [41]Savage, L. J. The foundations of statistics. [M]. New York: Wiley. 1954.

    [42]Schooler, L. J., &Hertwig, R. How forgetting aids heuristic inference. [J]. Psychological Review, 2005(112) 610-628.

    [43]Shepard, R. N. Evolution of a mesh between principles of the mind and regularities of the world. In J. Dupré (Ed.)[J]. The latest on the best: Essays on evolution and optimality. 1987.

    [44]Simon, H. A. A behavioral model of rational choice[J]. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1955(69) 99-118.

    [45]Simon, H. A. Rational choice and the structure of environments[J]. Psychological Review, 1956(63), 129-138.

    [46]Simon, H. A. Information processing models of cognition[J]. Annual Review of Psychology, 1979(30), 363-396.

    [47]Simon, H. A. Models of bounded rationality. [M]. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 1982.

    [48]Simon, H. A. Rationality in psychology and economics[J]. Journal of Business, 1986(59) S209-S224.

    [49 Slovic, P., & Lichtenstein, S. Preference reversals: A broader perspective[J]. American Economic Review, 1983(73), 596-605.

    [50]Smith, A. The wealth of nations (5th ed.)[M]. New York: The Modern Library, 1776.

    [51]Starmer, C. Experimental economics: Hard science or wasteful tinkering?[J]. Economic Journal, 1999(109), F5-F15.

    [52]Tversky, A., &Kahneman, D. Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases [J]. Science, 1974.(185) 1124-1131.

    [53]Tversky, A., &Kahneman, D. Rational choice and the framing of decisions[J]. Journal of Business, 1986(59), S251-S278.

    [54]Walras, L. Elements of Pure Economics. Tr. William Jaffe. [M]. London: George Allen &Unwin. 1954.

    *Jing Qian, Department of Psychology, School of Social Sciences, Tsinghua University, Beijing, China.

    Fund project: This research was funded by the Chinese National Science Foundation (CNSF: 71401089) and Tsinghua Research Initiation Fund (20151080447).

    一级毛片我不卡| 久久久精品94久久精品| 亚洲怡红院男人天堂| 汤姆久久久久久久影院中文字幕| 午夜影院在线不卡| 高清毛片免费看| 免费看日本二区| 麻豆成人午夜福利视频| 日韩亚洲欧美综合| 日韩免费高清中文字幕av| 六月丁香七月| 热re99久久国产66热| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜爱| 久久99热这里只频精品6学生| 亚洲内射少妇av| 高清av免费在线| 各种免费的搞黄视频| 我的女老师完整版在线观看| 色婷婷av一区二区三区视频| 搡女人真爽免费视频火全软件| 亚洲天堂av无毛| 如日韩欧美国产精品一区二区三区 | 欧美变态另类bdsm刘玥| av线在线观看网站| 久久99热6这里只有精品| 好男人视频免费观看在线| 精品卡一卡二卡四卡免费| 热re99久久国产66热| 99九九在线精品视频 | 十八禁网站网址无遮挡 | 自拍欧美九色日韩亚洲蝌蚪91 | 高清毛片免费看| 老熟女久久久| 久久精品国产亚洲av天美| 中文在线观看免费www的网站| 九九爱精品视频在线观看| 狠狠精品人妻久久久久久综合| 久久久久久久国产电影| 观看免费一级毛片| 日韩在线高清观看一区二区三区| 亚洲国产精品国产精品| 久久久久久久久大av| 这个男人来自地球电影免费观看 | 乱人伦中国视频| 亚洲精品日本国产第一区| 插阴视频在线观看视频| 亚洲综合精品二区| 高清欧美精品videossex| 在现免费观看毛片| 日韩亚洲欧美综合| 最近的中文字幕免费完整| 这个男人来自地球电影免费观看 | 国内精品宾馆在线| 国产精品嫩草影院av在线观看| 色吧在线观看| 菩萨蛮人人尽说江南好唐韦庄| 亚洲欧美精品自产自拍| 成年人免费黄色播放视频 | 亚洲天堂av无毛| 亚洲国产欧美在线一区| 搡老乐熟女国产| 欧美性感艳星| 免费观看性生交大片5| 亚洲婷婷狠狠爱综合网| 夜夜骑夜夜射夜夜干| 乱系列少妇在线播放| 超碰97精品在线观看| 精品亚洲成a人片在线观看| 成人美女网站在线观看视频| 美女中出高潮动态图| 人妻 亚洲 视频| 蜜桃在线观看..| 高清视频免费观看一区二区| www.av在线官网国产| 插逼视频在线观看| 汤姆久久久久久久影院中文字幕| 国产欧美日韩综合在线一区二区 | 久久影院123| 免费观看无遮挡的男女| 中文乱码字字幕精品一区二区三区| 国产精品久久久久久精品电影小说| 乱系列少妇在线播放| 欧美3d第一页| 99久久人妻综合| 日韩一区二区视频免费看| 中文资源天堂在线| 九草在线视频观看| 国产av码专区亚洲av| 人妻夜夜爽99麻豆av| 男人舔奶头视频| 成人国产麻豆网| 午夜激情久久久久久久| 久久午夜综合久久蜜桃| 久久精品久久精品一区二区三区| 精品国产国语对白av| 男人和女人高潮做爰伦理| 亚洲精品日本国产第一区| 亚洲国产精品成人久久小说| 最近的中文字幕免费完整| 国产一级毛片在线| 精品一区二区三卡| 国产精品国产av在线观看| 91精品一卡2卡3卡4卡| 性高湖久久久久久久久免费观看| 天堂中文最新版在线下载| 午夜日本视频在线| 黄片无遮挡物在线观看| 精品国产乱码久久久久久小说| 亚洲一级一片aⅴ在线观看| 午夜免费鲁丝| 午夜福利影视在线免费观看| 午夜激情福利司机影院| 免费看日本二区| 国产日韩欧美在线精品| 伦精品一区二区三区| 99视频精品全部免费 在线| 婷婷色麻豆天堂久久| av免费在线看不卡| 精品一区在线观看国产| 亚洲欧美清纯卡通| 人妻系列 视频| av在线app专区| 18+在线观看网站| 国产有黄有色有爽视频| 亚洲精品自拍成人| 国产一区二区在线观看日韩| 国产精品三级大全| 黄色毛片三级朝国网站 | av.在线天堂| 男人舔奶头视频| 国产成人91sexporn| 精品一区在线观看国产| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜爱| 色婷婷久久久亚洲欧美| 一级av片app| 中文字幕人妻熟人妻熟丝袜美| 国产精品国产av在线观看| 五月开心婷婷网| 男的添女的下面高潮视频| av播播在线观看一区| 日韩制服骚丝袜av| 成人特级av手机在线观看| 91久久精品国产一区二区成人| 久久国内精品自在自线图片| 婷婷色av中文字幕| 久久久久久久亚洲中文字幕| 内射极品少妇av片p| 亚洲av日韩在线播放| av福利片在线| 国产亚洲午夜精品一区二区久久| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜爱| 精品人妻熟女av久视频| 成年av动漫网址| 赤兔流量卡办理| 97在线人人人人妻| 一本一本综合久久| 国产一级毛片在线| 精品久久久噜噜| 五月开心婷婷网| 日韩一本色道免费dvd| 国产熟女午夜一区二区三区 | 777米奇影视久久| 啦啦啦视频在线资源免费观看| 最近2019中文字幕mv第一页| 欧美成人午夜免费资源| 一个人看视频在线观看www免费| 两个人的视频大全免费| 99热国产这里只有精品6| 一区二区三区四区激情视频| 97精品久久久久久久久久精品| 黄色欧美视频在线观看| 日韩熟女老妇一区二区性免费视频| 欧美亚洲 丝袜 人妻 在线| 国产男女内射视频| 久久99热这里只频精品6学生| 欧美精品亚洲一区二区| 夜夜爽夜夜爽视频| 夜夜爽夜夜爽视频| 成年人免费黄色播放视频 | 大码成人一级视频| 国产av国产精品国产| 亚洲av在线观看美女高潮| 日韩欧美一区视频在线观看 | 综合色丁香网| 国产精品久久久久成人av| 美女视频免费永久观看网站| 久久国产精品男人的天堂亚洲 | 少妇的逼好多水| 久久6这里有精品| 男人爽女人下面视频在线观看| 特大巨黑吊av在线直播| 久久久欧美国产精品| av有码第一页| 3wmmmm亚洲av在线观看| av天堂久久9| 热re99久久国产66热| 日韩伦理黄色片| 国产精品免费大片| 国语对白做爰xxxⅹ性视频网站| 久久99热6这里只有精品| 国产成人一区二区在线| 精品国产一区二区三区久久久樱花| 亚洲欧美精品专区久久| 一级二级三级毛片免费看| 天堂俺去俺来也www色官网| 久久久欧美国产精品| 亚洲一区二区三区欧美精品| 亚洲欧洲精品一区二区精品久久久 | 国产亚洲欧美精品永久| 黄色怎么调成土黄色| 精品一区二区三区视频在线| 国产亚洲精品久久久com| 爱豆传媒免费全集在线观看| 天堂8中文在线网| 一区二区三区免费毛片| 韩国av在线不卡| 丝袜喷水一区| 亚洲国产日韩一区二区| 亚洲av国产av综合av卡| 日本vs欧美在线观看视频 | 又爽又黄a免费视频| 看免费成人av毛片| 欧美精品一区二区免费开放| 黑人猛操日本美女一级片| 一本大道久久a久久精品| 九九爱精品视频在线观看| 久久久久久久久久成人| 日日啪夜夜撸| 97在线视频观看| 丝袜脚勾引网站| 亚洲av成人精品一区久久| 国产高清不卡午夜福利| 日韩制服骚丝袜av| 卡戴珊不雅视频在线播放| 韩国高清视频一区二区三区| 国产欧美日韩精品一区二区| 亚洲第一区二区三区不卡| 国产一区亚洲一区在线观看| 亚洲欧美清纯卡通| 亚洲图色成人| 女性生殖器流出的白浆| 一区在线观看完整版| 亚洲精品国产色婷婷电影| 麻豆成人午夜福利视频| 国产一区有黄有色的免费视频| 99视频精品全部免费 在线| 99久久精品热视频| 免费观看无遮挡的男女| 女的被弄到高潮叫床怎么办| 精品少妇黑人巨大在线播放| 街头女战士在线观看网站| 一级毛片电影观看| 51国产日韩欧美| 内射极品少妇av片p| 国产有黄有色有爽视频| 亚洲国产av新网站| 18禁在线无遮挡免费观看视频| 超碰97精品在线观看| 伦精品一区二区三区| 国产黄频视频在线观看| 成人影院久久| 欧美xxxx性猛交bbbb| 日韩一区二区视频免费看| 国产女主播在线喷水免费视频网站| 国产精品国产三级国产av玫瑰| 亚洲va在线va天堂va国产| 极品少妇高潮喷水抽搐| 国产精品一区二区在线观看99| 精品一区二区免费观看| 精品少妇久久久久久888优播| 婷婷色av中文字幕| 久久久久久久久久成人| 欧美日韩在线观看h| 天堂8中文在线网| 国产精品久久久久久久久免| 日本黄色日本黄色录像| 黄片无遮挡物在线观看| 亚洲国产精品一区三区| 国产亚洲一区二区精品| 欧美人与善性xxx| 欧美日韩视频精品一区| 精品少妇久久久久久888优播| 亚洲av综合色区一区| 黄色一级大片看看| 人人妻人人澡人人看| 亚洲高清免费不卡视频| 一级a做视频免费观看| 18禁在线无遮挡免费观看视频| 亚洲不卡免费看| 久久久久久久久久久免费av| 视频区图区小说| 亚洲精品国产av成人精品| 日本欧美视频一区| 国产女主播在线喷水免费视频网站| 大片电影免费在线观看免费| 女性被躁到高潮视频| 久久国产精品男人的天堂亚洲 | 一区二区三区乱码不卡18| 在线观看人妻少妇| 亚洲激情五月婷婷啪啪| 久久青草综合色| 亚洲美女搞黄在线观看| 国产高清不卡午夜福利| 女人精品久久久久毛片| 性色avwww在线观看| tube8黄色片| 精品人妻偷拍中文字幕| 在线观看国产h片| 欧美 日韩 精品 国产| 国产黄片美女视频| 精品久久久久久电影网| 一级毛片我不卡| 欧美97在线视频| 日韩人妻高清精品专区| 亚洲av电影在线观看一区二区三区| 韩国高清视频一区二区三区| 黄色配什么色好看| 亚洲美女视频黄频| 日韩免费高清中文字幕av| 男人添女人高潮全过程视频| 22中文网久久字幕| 男女国产视频网站| 成人二区视频| h日本视频在线播放| 国产男人的电影天堂91| 国产黄色视频一区二区在线观看| 尾随美女入室| 亚洲av成人精品一二三区| 99久久精品国产国产毛片| 久久婷婷青草| 汤姆久久久久久久影院中文字幕| 丰满迷人的少妇在线观看| 午夜精品国产一区二区电影| 精品国产露脸久久av麻豆| 一本—道久久a久久精品蜜桃钙片| 下体分泌物呈黄色| 国产精品不卡视频一区二区| 少妇被粗大猛烈的视频| 午夜福利影视在线免费观看| 亚洲国产毛片av蜜桃av| a级毛片在线看网站| 亚洲色图综合在线观看| 精品99又大又爽又粗少妇毛片| .国产精品久久| 少妇人妻久久综合中文| 热99国产精品久久久久久7| 秋霞伦理黄片| 深夜a级毛片| 99九九在线精品视频 | 精品久久久久久电影网| 日韩亚洲欧美综合| 亚洲无线观看免费| 看非洲黑人一级黄片| 久久国产亚洲av麻豆专区| 免费黄频网站在线观看国产| 国产精品国产三级专区第一集| 久久 成人 亚洲| 涩涩av久久男人的天堂| 日韩欧美 国产精品| 久久人人爽av亚洲精品天堂| 久久久久久久大尺度免费视频| 国产av精品麻豆| 国国产精品蜜臀av免费| 国产精品国产三级国产专区5o| 国产精品.久久久| 一边亲一边摸免费视频| 人妻系列 视频| 日韩熟女老妇一区二区性免费视频| 国产男人的电影天堂91| 欧美丝袜亚洲另类| av福利片在线观看| 少妇的逼好多水| 欧美日韩亚洲高清精品| 永久网站在线| 在线观看国产h片| 99久久人妻综合| 纵有疾风起免费观看全集完整版| 9色porny在线观看| 亚洲国产精品国产精品| 亚洲精品亚洲一区二区| 亚洲欧美日韩卡通动漫| 高清在线视频一区二区三区| 美女大奶头黄色视频| 精品少妇久久久久久888优播| 国产亚洲av片在线观看秒播厂| 久久热精品热| 久久 成人 亚洲| 久久精品熟女亚洲av麻豆精品| av播播在线观看一区| 免费黄色在线免费观看| 免费大片黄手机在线观看| 亚洲国产欧美在线一区| 99热这里只有是精品在线观看| 看十八女毛片水多多多| 日韩av免费高清视频| 亚洲国产欧美日韩在线播放 | 亚洲婷婷狠狠爱综合网| 成人午夜精彩视频在线观看| 99久久精品热视频| 国产精品久久久久久精品古装| 亚洲欧美一区二区三区黑人 | 18禁裸乳无遮挡动漫免费视频| 国产亚洲一区二区精品| 欧美最新免费一区二区三区| 亚洲天堂av无毛| 精品国产国语对白av| 在线观看免费视频网站a站| 午夜福利在线观看免费完整高清在| 2022亚洲国产成人精品| 久久久久久久久久人人人人人人| 欧美3d第一页| 啦啦啦中文免费视频观看日本| av又黄又爽大尺度在线免费看| 久久99一区二区三区| 你懂的网址亚洲精品在线观看| 婷婷色麻豆天堂久久| 高清不卡的av网站| 亚洲国产毛片av蜜桃av| 欧美日韩视频精品一区| 丝袜脚勾引网站| 色网站视频免费| 国产视频首页在线观看| 久热久热在线精品观看| 亚洲精品aⅴ在线观看| 免费观看无遮挡的男女| 国产午夜精品一二区理论片| 最近最新中文字幕免费大全7| 免费看日本二区| 日韩人妻高清精品专区| 成人无遮挡网站| 国产探花极品一区二区| 国产国拍精品亚洲av在线观看| 欧美日韩亚洲高清精品| 一区二区三区精品91| 亚洲精品日本国产第一区| 色94色欧美一区二区| 中国国产av一级| 中文字幕久久专区| 免费播放大片免费观看视频在线观看| 欧美精品亚洲一区二区| 美女脱内裤让男人舔精品视频| 天美传媒精品一区二区| av专区在线播放| 一级毛片 在线播放| 亚洲精品中文字幕在线视频 | 亚洲内射少妇av| 久久精品国产亚洲av天美| 这个男人来自地球电影免费观看 | 美女国产视频在线观看| 丝袜在线中文字幕| 精品人妻偷拍中文字幕| 最近手机中文字幕大全| 久久久久久久久久人人人人人人| 嫩草影院新地址| 97超碰精品成人国产| 日韩中文字幕视频在线看片| 噜噜噜噜噜久久久久久91| a级毛色黄片| 天堂中文最新版在线下载| 国产黄片视频在线免费观看| 少妇被粗大的猛进出69影院 | 亚洲精品国产av蜜桃| 日本与韩国留学比较| 女性被躁到高潮视频| h日本视频在线播放| 天堂8中文在线网| 人妻 亚洲 视频| 777米奇影视久久| 中文在线观看免费www的网站| 日本色播在线视频| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区| 在线看a的网站| 最近手机中文字幕大全| 亚洲中文av在线| 亚洲国产精品一区三区| 亚洲第一av免费看| 国产精品秋霞免费鲁丝片| 日本黄色片子视频| 美女大奶头黄色视频| 在现免费观看毛片| 人体艺术视频欧美日本| 国精品久久久久久国模美| 亚洲,欧美,日韩| 亚洲精品国产成人久久av| 亚洲av成人精品一区久久| 一区二区av电影网| 妹子高潮喷水视频| 日韩av在线免费看完整版不卡| 日韩免费高清中文字幕av| 黄色配什么色好看| 国产综合精华液| 成人午夜精彩视频在线观看| 久久久久视频综合| av在线app专区| 草草在线视频免费看| 一级av片app| 亚洲精品久久久久久婷婷小说| 亚洲国产精品成人久久小说| 九九在线视频观看精品| 亚洲成人手机| 日本黄色日本黄色录像| 男女边吃奶边做爰视频| 精品久久久噜噜| 一本色道久久久久久精品综合| 高清毛片免费看| 欧美日韩精品成人综合77777| 久久精品久久久久久久性| 蜜臀久久99精品久久宅男| 水蜜桃什么品种好| 亚洲中文av在线| 免费观看性生交大片5| 国产毛片在线视频| av天堂久久9| 国产伦精品一区二区三区四那| 国产男人的电影天堂91| 乱人伦中国视频| 美女主播在线视频| 国产精品伦人一区二区| 国产黄色免费在线视频| 国产成人aa在线观看| 国产精品一区二区性色av| 国语对白做爰xxxⅹ性视频网站| 成人亚洲欧美一区二区av| 18禁在线无遮挡免费观看视频| 国产一区二区三区综合在线观看 | av有码第一页| av国产精品久久久久影院| 不卡视频在线观看欧美| 欧美日韩视频高清一区二区三区二| 精品视频人人做人人爽| 大片电影免费在线观看免费| 夜夜爽夜夜爽视频| 亚洲自偷自拍三级| 国产色爽女视频免费观看| 久久久久久久久大av| 十八禁高潮呻吟视频 | 十八禁高潮呻吟视频 | 久久久国产欧美日韩av| 久久久久久伊人网av| 在线观看人妻少妇| 国产精品国产三级国产av玫瑰| videos熟女内射| 国产精品人妻久久久影院| 少妇精品久久久久久久| 久久久久视频综合| 免费黄频网站在线观看国产| 七月丁香在线播放| 国产亚洲av片在线观看秒播厂| 精品久久久久久电影网| 久久久久久人妻| 少妇人妻久久综合中文| 一个人免费看片子| 大码成人一级视频| 亚洲第一av免费看| 一边亲一边摸免费视频| 成年女人在线观看亚洲视频| 一级毛片电影观看| 日本欧美视频一区| 日本wwww免费看| 在线亚洲精品国产二区图片欧美 | 少妇被粗大猛烈的视频| 亚洲人成网站在线播| 少妇人妻 视频| 日日啪夜夜爽| h视频一区二区三区| 久久精品国产自在天天线| 婷婷色av中文字幕| 国产精品福利在线免费观看| 99热这里只有是精品在线观看| 国产精品福利在线免费观看| 性色av一级| 69精品国产乱码久久久| 三上悠亚av全集在线观看 | 六月丁香七月| .国产精品久久| 日韩免费高清中文字幕av| 免费观看av网站的网址| 国产在视频线精品| 99视频精品全部免费 在线| 一本一本综合久久| 边亲边吃奶的免费视频| 国产 精品1| 2022亚洲国产成人精品| 久久99热6这里只有精品| av免费观看日本| 久久久久久人妻| 成人国产av品久久久| 日本黄色日本黄色录像| 啦啦啦中文免费视频观看日本| 国产在线视频一区二区| 亚洲,一卡二卡三卡| 亚洲av二区三区四区| 亚洲综合精品二区| 日韩欧美 国产精品| 亚洲欧美日韩另类电影网站| 亚洲欧美精品专区久久| 18禁动态无遮挡网站| 日本vs欧美在线观看视频 | 九九久久精品国产亚洲av麻豆| 老熟女久久久| 成人国产av品久久久| 成人毛片a级毛片在线播放| 97精品久久久久久久久久精品| 欧美精品一区二区免费开放| 如何舔出高潮| 亚洲国产精品专区欧美| 精品亚洲成国产av| 2018国产大陆天天弄谢| 少妇被粗大的猛进出69影院 | 国产高清三级在线| 国产男女超爽视频在线观看| 大片免费播放器 马上看| 男女免费视频国产| 国产中年淑女户外野战色| 国产黄频视频在线观看|